Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals
by
Immanuel Kant, 1724-1804
(translated by Thomas Kingsmill Abbott)
eBooks@Adelaide
- 2009
This web edition published by http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/.
Rendered into HTML by Steve
Thomas.
Last updated Sat Jan 30 10:57:12 2010.
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Licence
(available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/2.5/au/).
You are free: to copy, distribute, display, and perform the work, and to
make derivative works under the following conditions: you must attribute the
work in the manner specified by the licensor; you may not use this work for
commercial purposes; if you alter, transform, or build upon this work, you
may distribute the resulting work only under a license identical to this
one. For any reuse or distribution, you must make clear to others the
license terms of this work. Any of these conditions can be waived if you get
permission from the licensor. Your fair use and other rights are in no way
affected by the above.
The complete work is also available as a single file, at http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/k/kant/immanuel/k16prm/complete.html
A MARC21 Catalogue record for this edition can be downloaded from http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/k/kant/immanuel/k16prm/marc.bib
eBooks@Adelaide
The University of Adelaide Library
University of Adelaide
South Australia 5005
Table of Contents
Preface
First
Section
Transition
from the Common Rational Knowledge of Morality to the Philosophical
Second
Section
Transition
from Popular Moral Philosophy to the Metaphysic of Morals
Third
Section
Transition
from the Metaphysic of Morals to the Critique of Pure Practical Reason
Preface
Ancient Greek philosophy was divided into three sciences: physics, ethics,
and logic. This division is perfectly suitable to the nature of the thing; and
the only improvement that can be made in it is to add the principle on which
it is based, so that we may both satisfy ourselves of its completeness, and
also be able to determine correctly the necessary subdivisions.
All rational knowledge is either material or formal: the former considers
some object, the latter is concerned only with the form of the understanding
and of the reason itself, and with the universal laws of thought in general
without distinction of its objects. Formal philosophy is called logic.
Material philosophy, however, has to do with determinate objects and the laws
to which they are subject, is again twofold; for these laws are either laws of
nature or of freedom. The science of the former is physics, that of the
latter, ethics; they are also called natural philosophy and moral philosophy
respectively.
Logic cannot have any empirical part; that is, a part in which the
universal and necessary laws of thought should rest on grounds taken from
experience; otherwise it would not be logic, i.e., a canon for the
understanding or the reason, valid for all thought, and capable of
demonstration. Natural and moral philosophy, on the contrary, can each have
their empirical part, since the former has to determine the laws of nature as
an object of experience; the latter the laws of the human will, so far as it
is affected by nature: the former, however, being laws according to which
everything does happen; the latter, laws according to which everything ought
to happen. Ethics, however, must also consider the conditions under which what
ought to happen frequently does not.
We may call all philosophy empirical, so far as it is based on grounds of
experience: on the other band, that which delivers its doctrines from a priori
principles alone we may call pure philosophy. When the latter is merely formal
it is logic; if it is restricted to definite objects of the understanding it
is metaphysic.
In this way there arises the idea of a twofold metaphysic — a metaphysic
of nature and a metaphysic of morals. Physics will thus have an empirical and
also a rational part. It is the same with Ethics; but here the empirical part
might have the special name of practical anthropology, the name morality being
appropriated to the rational part.
All trades, arts, and handiworks have gained by division of labour, namely,
when, instead of one man doing everything, each confines himself to a certain
kind of work distinct from others in the treatment it requires, so as to be
able to perform it with greater facility and in the greatest perfection. Where
the different kinds of work are not distinguished and divided, where everyone
is a jack-of-all-trades, there manufactures remain still in the greatest
barbarism. It might deserve to be considered whether pure philosophy in all
its parts does not require a man specially devoted to it, and whether it would
not be better for the whole business of science if those who, to please the
tastes of the public, are wont to blend the rational and empirical elements
together, mixed in all sorts of proportions unknown to themselves, and who
call themselves independent thinkers, giving the name of minute philosophers
to those who apply themselves to the rational part only — if these, I say,
were warned not to carry on two employments together which differ widely in
the treatment they demand, for each of which perhaps a special talent is
required, and the combination of which in one person only produces bunglers.
But I only ask here whether the nature of science does not require that we
should always carefully separate the empirical from the rational part, and
prefix to Physics proper (or empirical physics) a metaphysic of nature, and to
practical anthropology a metaphysic of morals, which must be carefully cleared
of everything empirical, so that we may know how much can be accomplished by
pure reason in both cases, and from what sources it draws this its a priori
teaching, and that whether the latter inquiry is conducted by all moralists
(whose name is legion), or only by some who feel a calling thereto.
As my concern here is with moral philosophy, I limit the question suggested
to this: Whether it is not of the utmost necessity to construct a pure thing
which is only empirical and which belongs to anthropology? for that such a
philosophy must be possible is evident from the common idea of duty and of the
moral laws. Everyone must admit that if a law is to have moral force, i.e., to
be the basis of an obligation, it must carry with it absolute necessity; that,
for example, the precept, "Thou shalt not lie," is not valid for men
alone, as if other rational beings had no need to observe it; and so with all
the other moral laws properly so called; that, therefore, the basis of
obligation must not be sought in the nature of man, or in the circumstances in
the world in which he is placed, but a priori simply in the conception of pure
reason; and although any other precept which is founded on principles of mere
experience may be in certain respects universal, yet in as far as it rests
even in the least degree on an empirical basis, perhaps only as to a motive,
such a precept, while it may be a practical rule, can never be called a moral
law.
Thus not only are moral laws with their principles essentially
distinguished from every other kind of practical knowledge in which there is
anything empirical, but all moral philosophy rests wholly on its pure part.
When applied to man, it does not borrow the least thing from the knowledge of
man himself (anthropology), but gives laws a priori to him as a rational
being. No doubt these laws require a judgement sharpened by experience, in
order on the one hand to distinguish in what cases they are applicable, and on
the other to procure for them access to the will of the man and effectual
influence on conduct; since man is acted on by so many inclinations that,
though capable of the idea of a practical pure reason, he is not so easily
able to make it effective in concreto in his life.
A metaphysic of morals is therefore indispensably necessary, not merely for
speculative reasons, in order to investigate the sources of the practical
principles which are to be found a priori in our reason, but also because
morals themselves are liable to all sorts of corruption, as long as we are
without that clue and supreme canon by which to estimate them correctly. For
in order that an action should be morally good, it is not enough that it
conform to the moral law, but it must also be done for the sake of the law,
otherwise that conformity is only very contingent and uncertain; since a
principle which is not moral, although it may now and then produce actions
conformable to the law, will also often produce actions which contradict it.
Now it is only a pure philosophy that we can look for the moral law in its
purity and genuineness (and, in a practical matter, this is of the utmost
consequence): we must, therefore, begin with pure philosophy (metaphysic), and
without it there cannot be any moral philosophy at all. That which mingles
these pure principles with the empirical does not deserve the name of
philosophy (for what distinguishes philosophy from common rational knowledge
is that it treats in separate sciences what the latter only comprehends
confusedly); much less does it deserve that of moral philosophy, since by this
confusion it even spoils the purity of morals themselves, and counteracts its
own end.
Let it not be thought, however, that what is here demanded is already
extant in the propaedeutic prefixed by the celebrated Wolf to his moral
philosophy, namely, his so-called general practical philosophy, and that,
therefore, we have not to strike into an entirely new field. just because it
was to be a general practical philosophy, it has not taken into consideration
a will of any particular kind — say one which should be determined solely
from a priori principles without any empirical motives, and which we might
call a pure will, but volition in general, with all the actions and conditions
which belong to it in this general signification. By this it is distinguished
from a metaphysic of morals, just as general logic, which treats of the acts
and canons of thought in general, is distinguished from transcendental
philosophy, which treats of the particular acts and canons of pure thought,
i.e., that whose cognitions are altogether a priori. For the metaphysic of
morals has to examine the idea and the principles of a possible pure will, and
not the acts and conditions of human volition generally, which for the most
part are drawn from psychology. It is true that moral laws and duty are spoken
of in the general moral philosophy (contrary indeed to all fitness). But this
is no objection, for in this respect also the authors of that science remain
true to their idea of it; they do not distinguish the motives which are
prescribed as such by reason alone altogether a priori, and which are properly
moral, from the empirical motives which the understanding raises to general
conceptions merely by comparison of experiences; but, without noticing the
difference of their sources, and looking on them all as homogeneous, they
consider only their greater or less amount. It is in this way they frame their
notion of obligation, which, though anything but moral, is all that can be
attained in a philosophy which passes no judgement at all on the origin of all
possible practical concepts, whether they are a priori, or only a posteriori.
Intending to publish hereafter a metaphysic of morals, I issue in the first
instance these fundamental principles. Indeed there is properly no other
foundation for it than the critical examination of a pure practical Reason;
just as that of metaphysics is the critical examination of the pure
speculative reason, already published. But in the first place the former is
not so absolutely necessary as the latter, because in moral concerns human
reason can easily be brought to a high degree of correctness and completeness,
even in the commonest understanding, while on the contrary in its theoretic
but pure use it is wholly dialectical; and in the second place if the critique
of a pure practical reason is to be complete, it must be possible at the same
time to show its identity with the speculative reason in a common principle,
for it can ultimately be only one and the same reason which has to be
distinguished merely in its application. I could not, however, bring it to
such completeness here, without introducing considerations of a wholly
different kind, which would be perplexing to the reader. On this account I
have adopted the title of Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals
instead of that of a Critical Examination of the pure practical reason.
But in the third place, since a metaphysic of morals, in spite of the
discouraging title, is yet capable of being presented in popular form, and one
adapted to the common understanding, I find it useful to separate from it this
preliminary treatise on its fundamental principles, in order that I may not
hereafter have need to introduce these necessarily subtle discussions into a
book of a more simple character.
The present treatise is, however, nothing more than the investigation and
establishment of the supreme principle of morality, and this alone constitutes
a study complete in itself and one which ought to be kept apart from every
other moral investigation. No doubt my conclusions on this weighty question,
which has hitherto been very unsatisfactorily examined, would receive much
light from the application of the same principle to the whole system, and
would be greatly confirmed by the adequacy which it exhibits throughout; but I
must forego this advantage, which indeed would be after all more gratifying
than useful, since the easy applicability of a principle and its apparent
adequacy give no very certain proof of its soundness, but rather inspire a
certain partiality, which prevents us from examining and estimating it
strictly in itself and without regard to consequences.
I have adopted in this work the method which I think most suitable,
proceeding analytically from common knowledge to the determination of its
ultimate principle, and again descending synthetically from the examination of
this principle and its sources to the common knowledge in which we find it
employed. The division will, therefore, be as follows:
First
section. Transition from the common rational knowledge of morality to the
philosophical.
Second
section. Transition from popular moral philosophy to the metaphysic of
morals.
Third
section. Final step from the metaphysic of morals to the critique of the
pure practical reason.
First Section
Transition from the Common Rational Knowledge of Morality to the
Philosophical
Nothing can possibly be conceived in the world, or even out of it, which
can be called good, without qualification, except a good will. Intelligence,
wit, judgement, and the other talents of the mind, however they may be named,
or courage, resolution, perseverance, as qualities of temperament, are
undoubtedly good and desirable in many respects; but these gifts of nature may
also become extremely bad and mischievous if the will which is to make use of
them, and which, therefore, constitutes what is called character, is not good.
It is the same with the gifts of fortune. Power, riches, honour, even health,
and the general well-being and contentment with one's condition which is
called happiness, inspire pride, and often presumption, if there is not a good
will to correct the influence of these on the mind, and with this also to
rectify the whole principle of acting and adapt it to its end. The sight of a
being who is not adorned with a single feature of a pure and good will,
enjoying unbroken prosperity, can never give pleasure to an impartial rational
spectator. Thus a good will appears to constitute the indispensable condition
even of being worthy of happiness.
There are even some qualities which are of service to this good will itself
and may facilitate its action, yet which have no intrinsic unconditional
value, but always presuppose a good will, and this qualifies the esteem that
we justly have for them and does not permit us to regard them as absolutely
good. Moderation in the affections and passions, self-control, and calm
deliberation are not only good in many respects, but even seem to constitute
part of the intrinsic worth of the person; but they are far from deserving to
be called good without qualification, although they have been so
unconditionally praised by the ancients. For without the principles of a good
will, they may become extremely bad, and the coolness of a villain not only
makes him far more dangerous, but also directly makes him more abominable in
our eyes than he would have been without it.
A good will is good not because of what it performs or effects, not by its
aptness for the attainment of some proposed end, but simply by virtue of the
volition; that is, it is good in itself, and considered by itself is to be
esteemed much higher than all that can be brought about by it in favour of any
inclination, nay even of the sum total of all inclinations. Even if it should
happen that, owing to special disfavour of fortune, or the niggardly provision
of a step-motherly nature, this will should wholly lack power to accomplish
its purpose, if with its greatest efforts it should yet achieve nothing, and
there should remain only the good will (not, to be sure, a mere wish, but the
summoning of all means in our power), then, like a jewel, it would still shine
by its own light, as a thing which has its whole value in itself. Its
usefulness or fruitfulness can neither add nor take away anything from this
value. It would be, as it were, only the setting to enable us to handle it the
more conveniently in common commerce, or to attract to it the attention of
those who are not yet connoisseurs, but not to recommend it to true
connoisseurs, or to determine its value.
There is, however, something so strange in this idea of the absolute value
of the mere will, in which no account is taken of its utility, that
notwithstanding the thorough assent of even common reason to the idea, yet a
suspicion must arise that it may perhaps really be the product of mere
high-flown fancy, and that we may have misunderstood the purpose of nature in
assigning reason as the governor of our will. Therefore we will examine this
idea from this point of view.
In the physical constitution of an organized being, that is, a being
adapted suitably to the purposes of life, we assume it as a fundamental
principle that no organ for any purpose will be found but what is also the
fittest and best adapted for that purpose. Now in a being which has reason and
a will, if the proper object of nature were its conservation, its welfare, in
a word, its happiness, then nature would have hit upon a very bad arrangement
in selecting the reason of the creature to carry out this purpose. For all the
actions which the creature has to perform with a view to this purpose, and the
whole rule of its conduct, would be far more surely prescribed to it by
instinct, and that end would have been attained thereby much more certainly
than it ever can be by reason. Should reason have been communicated to this
favoured creature over and above, it must only have served it to contemplate
the happy constitution of its nature, to admire it, to congratulate itself
thereon, and to feel thankful for it to the beneficent cause, but not that it
should subject its desires to that weak and delusive guidance and meddle
bunglingly with the purpose of nature. In a word, nature would have taken care
that reason should not break forth into practical exercise, nor have the
presumption, with its weak insight, to think out for itself the plan of
happiness, and of the means of attaining it. Nature would not only have taken
on herself the choice of the ends, but also of the means, and with wise
foresight would have entrusted both to instinct.
And, in fact, we find that the more a cultivated reason applies itself with
deliberate purpose to the enjoyment of life and happiness, so much the more
does the man fail of true satisfaction. And from this circumstance there
arises in many, if they are candid enough to confess it, a certain degree of
misology, that is, hatred of reason, especially in the case of those who are
most experienced in the use of it, because after calculating all the
advantages they derive, I do not say from the invention of all the arts of
common luxury, but even from the sciences (which seem to them to be after all
only a luxury of the understanding), they find that they have, in fact, only
brought more trouble on their shoulders. rather than gained in happiness; and
they end by envying, rather than despising, the more common stamp of men who
keep closer to the guidance of mere instinct and do not allow their reason
much influence on their conduct. And this we must admit, that the judgement of
those who would very much lower the lofty eulogies of the advantages which
reason gives us in regard to the happiness and satisfaction of life, or who
would even reduce them below zero, is by no means morose or ungrateful to the
goodness with which the world is governed, but that there lies at the root of
these judgements the idea that our existence has a different and far nobler
end, for which, and not for happiness, reason is properly intended, and which
must, therefore, be regarded as the supreme condition to which the private
ends of man must, for the most part, be postponed.
For as reason is not competent to guide the will with certainty in regard
to its objects and the satisfaction of all our wants (which it to some extent
even multiplies), this being an end to which an implanted instinct would have
led with much greater certainty; and since, nevertheless, reason is imparted
to us as a practical faculty, i.e., as one which is to have influence on the
will, therefore, admitting that nature generally in the distribution of her
capacities has adapted the means to the end, its true destination must be to
produce a will, not merely good as a means to something else, but good in
itself, for which reason was absolutely necessary. This will then, though not
indeed the sole and complete good, must be the supreme good and the condition
of every other, even of the desire of happiness. Under these circumstances,
there is nothing inconsistent with the wisdom of nature in the fact that the
cultivation of the reason, which is requisite for the first and unconditional
purpose, does in many ways interfere, at least in this life, with the
attainment of the second, which is always conditional, namely, happiness. Nay,
it may even reduce it to nothing, without nature thereby failing of her
purpose. For reason recognizes the establishment of a good will as its highest
practical destination, and in attaining this purpose is capable only of a
satisfaction of its own proper kind, namely that from the attainment of an
end, which end again is determined by reason only, notwithstanding that this
may involve many a disappointment to the ends of inclination.
We have then to develop the notion of a will which deserves to be highly
esteemed for itself and is good without a view to anything further, a notion
which exists already in the sound natural understanding, requiring rather to
be cleared up than to be taught, and which in estimating the value of our
actions always takes the first place and constitutes the condition of all the
rest. In order to do this, we will take the notion of duty, which includes
that of a good will, although implying certain subjective restrictions and
hindrances. These, however, far from concealing it, or rendering it
unrecognizable, rather bring it out by contrast and make it shine forth so
much the brighter.
I omit here all actions which are already recognized as inconsistent with
duty, although they may be useful for this or that purpose, for with these the
question whether they are done from duty cannot arise at all, since they even
conflict with it. I also set aside those actions which really conform to duty,
but to which men have no direct inclination, performing them because they are
impelled thereto by some other inclination. For in this case we can readily
distinguish whether the action which agrees with duty is done from duty, or
from a selfish view. It is much harder to make this distinction when the
action accords with duty and the subject has besides a direct inclination to
it. For example, it is always a matter of duty that a dealer should not over
charge an inexperienced purchaser; and wherever there is much commerce the
prudent tradesman does not overcharge, but keeps a fixed price for everyone,
so that a child buys of him as well as any other. Men are thus honestly
served; but this is not enough to make us believe that the tradesman has so
acted from duty and from principles of honesty: his own advantage required it;
it is out of the question in this case to suppose that he might besides have a
direct inclination in favour of the buyers, so that, as it were, from love he
should give no advantage to one over another. Accordingly the action was done
neither from duty nor from direct inclination, but merely with a selfish view.
On the other hand, it is a duty to maintain one's life; and, in addition,
everyone has also a direct inclination to do so. But on this account the of
anxious care which most men take for it has no intrinsic worth, and their
maxim has no moral import. They preserve their life as duty requires, no
doubt, but not because duty requires. On the other band, if adversity and
hopeless sorrow have completely taken away the relish for life; if the
unfortunate one, strong in mind, indignant at his fate rather than desponding
or dejected, wishes for death, and yet preserves his life without loving it
— not from inclination or fear, but from duty — then his maxim has a moral
worth.
To be beneficent when we can is a duty; and besides this, there are many
minds so sympathetically constituted that, without any other motive of vanity
or self-interest, they find a pleasure in spreading joy around them and can
take delight in the satisfaction of others so far as it is their own work. But
I maintain that in such a case an action of this kind, however proper, however
amiable it may be, bas nevertheless no true moral worth, but is on a level
with other inclinations, e.g., the inclination to honour, which, if it is
happily directed to that which is in fact of public utility and accordant with
duty and consequently honourable, deserves praise and encouragement, but not
esteem. For the maxim lacks the moral import, namely, that such actions be
done from duty, not from inclination. Put the case that the mind of that
philanthropist were clouded by sorrow of his own, extinguishing all sympathy
with the lot of others, and that, while he still has the power to benefit
others in distress, he is not touched by their trouble because he is absorbed
with his own; and now suppose that he tears himself out of this dead
insensibility, and performs the action without any inclination to it, but
simply from duty, then first has his action its genuine moral worth. Further
still; if nature bas put little sympathy in the heart of this or that man; if
he, supposed to be an upright man, is by temperament cold and indifferent to
the sufferings of others, perhaps because in respect of his own he is provided
with the special gift of patience and fortitude and supposes, or even
requires, that others should have the same — and such a man would certainly
not be the meanest product of nature — but if nature had not specially
framed him for a philanthropist, would he not still find in himself a source
from whence to give himself a far higher worth than that of a good-natured
temperament could be? Unquestionably. It is just in this that the moral worth
of the character is brought out which is incomparably the highest of all,
namely, that he is beneficent, not from inclination, but from duty.
To secure one's own happiness is a duty, at least indirectly; for
discontent with one's condition, under a pressure of many anxieties and amidst
unsatisfied wants, might easily become a great temptation to transgression of
duty. But here again, without looking to duty, all men have already the
strongest and most intimate inclination to happiness, because it is just in
this idea that all inclinations are combined in one total. But the precept of
happiness is often of such a sort that it greatly interferes with some
inclinations, and yet a man cannot form any definite and certain conception of
the sum of satisfaction of all of them which is called happiness. It is not
then to be wondered at that a single inclination, definite both as to what it
promises and as to the time within which it can be gratified, is often able to
overcome such a fluctuating idea, and that a gouty patient, for instance, can
choose to enjoy what he likes, and to suffer what he may, since, according to
his calculation, on this occasion at least, be has not sacrificed the
enjoyment of the present moment to a possibly mistaken expectation of a
happiness which is supposed to be found in health. But even in this case, if
the general desire for happiness did not influence his will, and supposing
that in his particular case health was not a necessary element in this
calculation, there yet remains in this, as in all other cases, this law,
namely, that he should promote his happiness not from inclination but from
duty, and by this would his conduct first acquire true moral worth.
It is in this manner, undoubtedly, that we are to understand those passages
of Scripture also in which we are commanded to love our neighbour, even our
enemy. For love, as an affection, cannot be commanded, but beneficence for
duty's sake may; even though we are not impelled to it by any inclination —
nay, are even repelled by a natural and unconquerable aversion. This is
practical love and not pathological — a love which is seated in the will,
and not in the propensions of sense — in principles of action and not of
tender sympathy; and it is this love alone which can be commanded.
The second proposition is: That an action done from duty derives its moral
worth, not from the purpose which is to be attained by it, but from the maxim
by which it is determined, and therefore does not depend on the realization of
the object of the action, but merely on the principle of volition by which the
action has taken place, without regard to any object of desire. It is clear
from what precedes that the purposes which we may have in view in our actions,
or their effects regarded as ends and springs of the will, cannot give to
actions any unconditional or moral worth. In what, then, can their worth lie,
if it is not to consist in the will and in reference to its expected effect?
It cannot lie anywhere but in the principle of the will without regard to the
ends which can be attained by the action. For the will stands between its a
priori principle, which is formal, and its a posteriori spring, which is
material, as between two roads, and as it must be determined by something, it
that it must be determined by the formal principle of volition when an action
is done from duty, in which case every material principle has been withdrawn
from it.
The third proposition, which is a consequence of the two preceding, I would
express thus Duty is the necessity of acting from respect for the law. I may
have inclination for an object as the effect of my proposed action, but I
cannot have respect for it, just for this reason, that it is an effect and not
an energy of will. Similarly I cannot have respect for inclination, whether my
own or another's; I can at most, if my own, approve it; if another's,
sometimes even love it; i.e., look on it as favourable to my own interest. It
is only what is connected with my will as a principle, by no means as an
effect — what does not subserve my inclination, but overpowers it, or at
least in case of choice excludes it from its calculation — in other words,
simply the law of itself, which can be an object of respect, and hence a
command. Now an action done from duty must wholly exclude the influence of
inclination and with it every object of the will, so that nothing remains
which can determine the will except objectively the law, and subjectively pure
respect for this practical law, and consequently the maxim*
that I should follow this law even to the thwarting of all my inclinations.
* A maxim is the subjective principle of volition.
The objective principle (i.e., that which would also serve subjectively as a
practical principle to all rational beings if reason had full power over the
faculty of desire) is the practical law.
Thus the moral worth of an action does not lie in the effect expected from
it, nor in any principle of action which requires to borrow its motive from
this expected effect. For all these effects agreeableness of one's condition
and even the promotion of the happiness of others — could have been also
brought about by other causes, so that for this there would have been no need
of the will of a rational being; whereas it is in this alone that the supreme
and unconditional good can be found. The pre-eminent good which we call moral
can therefore consist in nothing else than the conception of law in itself,
which certainly is only possible in a rational being, in so far as this
conception, and not the expected effect, determines the will. This is a good
which is already present in the person who acts accordingly, and we have not
to wait for it to appear first in the result.*
* It might be here objected to me that I take refuge
behind the word respect in an obscure feeling, instead of giving a distinct
solution of the question by a concept of the reason. But although respect is a
feeling, it is not a feeling received through influence, but is self-wrought
by a rational concept, and, therefore, is specifically distinct from all
feelings of the former kind, which may be referred either to inclination or
fear, What I recognise immediately as a law for me, I recognise with respect.
This merely signifies the consciousness that my will is subordinate to a law,
without the intervention of other influences on my sense. The immediate
determination of the will by the law, and the consciousness of this, is called
respect, so that this is regarded as an effect of the law on the subject, and
not as the cause of it. Respect is properly the conception of a worth which
thwarts my self-love. Accordingly it is something which is considered neither
as an object of inclination nor of fear, although it has something analogous
to both. The object of respect is the law only, and that the law which we
impose on ourselves and yet recognise as necessary in itself. As a law, we are
subjected too it without consulting self-love; as imposed by us on ourselves,
it is a result of our will. In the former aspect it has an analogy to fear, in
the latter to inclination. Respect for a person is properly only respect for
the law (of honesty, etc.) of which he gives us an example. Since we also look
on the improvement of our talents as a duty, we consider that we see in a
person of talents, as it were, the example of a law (viz., to become like him
in this by exercise), and this constitutes our respect. All so-called moral
interest consists simply in respect for the law.
But what sort of law can that be, the conception of which must determine
the will, even without paying any regard to the effect expected from it, in
order that this will may be called good absolutely and without qualification?
As I have deprived the will of every impulse which could arise to it from
obedience to any law, there remains nothing but the universal conformity of
its actions to law in general, which alone is to serve the will as a
principle, i.e., I am never to act otherwise than so that I could also will
that my maxim should become a universal law. Here, now, it is the simple
conformity to law in general, without assuming any particular law applicable
to certain actions, that serves the will as its principle and must so serve
it, if duty is not to be a vain delusion and a chimerical notion. The common
reason of men in its practical judgements perfectly coincides with this and
always has in view the principle here suggested. Let the question be, for
example: May I when in distress make a promise with the intention not to keep
it? I readily distinguish here between the two significations which the
question may have: Whether it is prudent, or whether it is right, to make a
false promise? The former may undoubtedly of be the case. I see clearly indeed
that it is not enough to extricate myself from a present difficulty by means
of this subterfuge, but it must be well considered whether there may not
hereafter spring from this lie much greater inconvenience than that from which
I now free myself, and as, with all my supposed cunning, the consequences
cannot be so easily foreseen but that credit once lost may be much more
injurious to me than any mischief which I seek to avoid at present, it should
be considered whether it would not be more prudent to act herein according to
a universal maxim and to make it a habit to promise nothing except with the
intention of keeping it. But it is soon clear to me that such a maxim will
still only be based on the fear of consequences. Now it is a wholly different
thing to be truthful from duty and to be so from apprehension of injurious
consequences. In the first case, the very notion of the action already implies
a law for me; in the second case, I must first look about elsewhere to see
what results may be combined with it which would affect myself. For to deviate
from the principle of duty is beyond all doubt wicked; but to be unfaithful to
my maxim of prudence may often be very advantageous to me, although to abide
by it is certainly safer. The shortest way, however, and an unerring one, to
discover the answer to this question whether a lying promise is consistent
with duty, is to ask myself, "Should I be content that my maxim (to
extricate myself from difficulty by a false promise) should hold good as a
universal law, for myself as well as for others? and should I be able to say
to myself, "Every one may make a deceitful promise when he finds himself
in a difficulty from which he cannot otherwise extricate himself?" Then I
presently become aware that while I can will the lie, I can by no means will
that lying should be a universal law. For with such a law there would be no
promises at all, since it would be in vain to allege my intention in regard to
my future actions to those who would not believe this allegation, or if they
over hastily did so would pay me back in my own coin. Hence my maxim, as soon
as it should be made a universal law, would necessarily destroy itself.
I do not, therefore, need any far-reaching penetration to discern what I
have to do in order that my will may be morally good. Inexperienced in the
course of the world, incapable of being prepared for all its contingencies, I
only ask myself: Canst thou also will that thy maxim should be a universal
law? If not, then it must be rejected, and that not because of a disadvantage
accruing from it to myself or even to others, but because it cannot enter as a
principle into a possible universal legislation, and reason extorts from me
immediate respect for such legislation. I do not indeed as yet discern on what
this respect is based (this the philosopher may inquire), but at least I
understand this, that it is an estimation of the worth which far outweighs all
worth of what is recommended by inclination, and that the necessity of acting
from pure respect for the practical law is what constitutes duty, to which
every other motive must give place, because it is the condition of a will
being good in itself, and the worth of such a will is above everything.
Thus, then, without quitting the moral knowledge of common human reason, we
have arrived at its principle. And although, no doubt, common men do not
conceive it in such an abstract and universal form, yet they always have it
really before their eyes and use it as the standard of their decision. Here it
would be easy to show how, with this compass in hand, men are well able to
distinguish, in every case that occurs, what is good, what bad, conformably to
duty or inconsistent with it, if, without in the least teaching them anything
new, we only, like Socrates, direct their attention to the principle they
themselves employ; and that, therefore, we do not need science and philosophy
to know what we should do to be honest and good, yea, even wise and virtuous.
Indeed we might well have conjectured beforehand that the knowledge of what
every man is bound to do, and therefore also to know, would be within the
reach of every man, even the commonest. Here we cannot forbear admiration when
we see how great an advantage the practical judgement has over the theoretical
in the common understanding of men. In the latter, if common reason ventures
to depart from the laws of experience and from the perceptions of the senses,
it falls into mere inconceivabilities and self-contradictions, at least into a
chaos of uncertainty, obscurity, and instability. But in the practical sphere
it is just when the common understanding excludes all sensible springs from
practical laws that its power of judgement begins to show itself to advantage.
It then becomes even subtle, whether it be that it chicanes with its own
conscience or with other claims respecting what is to be called right, or
whether it desires for its own instruction to determine honestly the worth of
actions; and, in the latter case, it may even have as good a hope of hitting
the mark as any philosopher whatever can promise himself. Nay, it is almost
more sure of doing so, because the philosopher cannot have any other
principle, while he may easily perplex his judgement by a multitude of
considerations foreign to the matter, and so turn aside from the right way.
Would it not therefore be wiser in moral concerns to acquiesce in the
judgement of common reason, or at most only to call in philosophy for the
purpose of rendering the system of morals more complete and intelligible, and
its rules more convenient for use (especially for disputation), but not so as
to draw off the common understanding from its happy simplicity, or to bring it
by means of philosophy into a new path of inquiry and instruction?
Innocence is indeed a glorious thing; only, on the other hand, it is very
sad that it cannot well maintain itself and is easily seduced. On this account
even wisdom — which otherwise consists more in conduct than in knowledge —
yet has need of science, not in order to learn from it, but to secure for its
precepts admission and permanence. Against all the commands of duty which
reason represents to man as so deserving of respect, he feels in himself a
powerful counterpoise in his wants and inclinations, the entire satisfaction
of which he sums up under the name of happiness. Now reason issues its
commands unyieldingly, without promising anything to the inclinations, and, as
it were, with disregard and contempt for these claims, which are so impetuous,
and at the same time so plausible, and which will not allow themselves to be
suppressed by any command. Hence there arises a natural dialectic, i.e., a
disposition, to argue against these strict laws of duty and to question their
validity, or at least their purity and strictness; and, if possible, to make
them more accordant with our wishes and inclinations, that is to say, to
corrupt them at their very source, and entirely to destroy their worth — a
thing which even common practical reason cannot ultimately call good.
Thus is the common reason of man compelled to go out of its sphere, and to
take a step into the field of a practical philosophy, not to satisfy any
speculative want (which never occurs to it as long as it is content to be mere
sound reason), but even on practical grounds, in order to attain in it
information and clear instruction respecting the source of its principle, and
the correct determination of it in opposition to the maxims which are based on
wants and inclinations, so that it may escape from the perplexity of opposite
claims and not run the risk of losing all genuine moral principles through the
equivocation into which it easily falls. Thus, when practical reason
cultivates itself, there insensibly arises in it a dialetic which forces it to
seek aid in philosophy, just as happens to it in its theoretic use; and in
this case, therefore, as well as in the other, it will find rest nowhere but
in a thorough critical examination of our reason.
Second Section
Transition from Popular Moral Philosophy to the Metaphysic of Morals
If we have hitherto drawn our notion of duty from the common use of our
practical reason, it is by no means to be inferred that we have treated it as
an empirical notion. On the contrary, if we attend to the experience of men's
conduct, we meet frequent and, as we ourselves allow, just complaints that one
cannot find a single certain example of the disposition to act from pure duty.
Although many things are done in conformity with what duty prescribes, it is
nevertheless always doubtful whether they are done strictly from duty, so as
to have a moral worth. Hence there have at all times been philosophers who
have altogether denied that this disposition actually exists at all in human
actions, and have ascribed everything to a more or less refined self-love. Not
that they have on that account questioned the soundness of the conception of
morality; on the contrary, they spoke with sincere regret of the frailty and
corruption of human nature, which, though noble enough to take its rule an
idea so worthy of respect, is yet weak to follow it and employs reason which
ought to give it the law only for the purpose of providing for the interest of
the inclinations, whether singly or at the best in the greatest possible
harmony with one another.
In fact, it is absolutely impossible to make out by experience with
complete certainty a single case in which the maxim of an action, however
right in itself, rested simply on moral grounds and on the conception of duty.
Sometimes it happens that with the sharpest self-examination we can find
nothing beside the moral principle of duty which could have been powerful
enough to move us to this or that action and to so great a sacrifice; yet we
cannot from this infer with certainty that it was not really some secret
impulse of self-love, under the false appearance of duty, that was the actual
determining cause of the will. We like them to flatter ourselves by falsely
taking credit for a more noble motive; whereas in fact we can never, even by
the strictest examination, get completely behind the secret springs of action;
since, when the question is of moral worth, it is not with the actions which
we see that we are concerned, but with those inward principles of them which
we do not see.
Moreover, we cannot better serve the wishes of those who ridicule all
morality as a mere chimera of human imagination over stepping itself from
vanity, than by conceding to them that notions of duty must be drawn only from
experience (as from indolence, people are ready to think is also the case with
all other notions); for or is to prepare for them a certain triumph. I am
willing to admit out of love of humanity that even most of our actions are
correct, but if we look closer at them we everywhere come upon the dear self
which is always prominent, and it is this they have in view and not the strict
command of duty which would often require self-denial. Without being an enemy
of virtue, a cool observer, one that does not mistake the wish for good,
however lively, for its reality, may sometimes doubt whether true virtue is
actually found anywhere in the world, and this especially as years increase
and the judgement is partly made wiser by experience and partly, also, more
acute in observation. This being so, nothing can secure us from falling away
altogether from our ideas of duty, or maintain in the soul a well-grounded
respect for its law, but the clear conviction that although there should never
have been actions which really sprang from such pure sources, yet whether this
or that takes place is not at all the question; but that reason of itself,
independent on all experience, ordains what ought to take place, that
accordingly actions of which perhaps the world has hitherto never given an
example, the feasibility even of which might be very much doubted by one who
founds everything on experience, are nevertheless inflexibly commanded by
reason; that, e.g., even though there might never yet have been a sincere
friend, yet not a whit the less is pure sincerity in friendship required of
every man, because, prior to all experience, this duty is involved as duty in
the idea of a reason determining the will by a priori principles.
When we add further that, unless we deny that the notion of morality has
any truth or reference to any possible object, we must admit that its law must
be valid, not merely for men but for all rational creatures generally, not
merely under certain contingent conditions or with exceptions but with
absolute necessity, then it is clear that no experience could enable us to
infer even the possibility of such apodeictic laws. For with what right could
we bring into unbounded respect as a universal precept for every rational
nature that which perhaps holds only under the contingent conditions of
humanity? Or how could laws of the determination of our will be regarded as
laws of the determination of the will of rational beings generally, and for us
only as such, if they were merely empirical and did not take their origin
wholly a priori from pure but practical reason?
Nor could anything be more fatal to morality than that we should wish to
derive it from examples. For every example of it that is set before me must be
first itself tested by principles of morality, whether it is worthy to serve
as an original example, i.e., as a pattern; but by no means can it
authoritatively furnish the conception of morality. Even the Holy One of the
Gospels must first be compared with our ideal of moral perfection before we
can recognise Him as such; and so He says of Himself, "Why call ye Me
(whom you see) good; none is good (the model of good) but God only (whom ye do
not see)?" But whence have we the conception of God as the supreme good?
Simply from the idea of moral perfection, which reason frames a priori and
connects inseparably with the notion of a free will. Imitation finds no place
at all in morality, and examples serve only for encouragement, i.e., they put
beyond doubt the feasibility of what the law commands, they make visible that
which the practical rule expresses more generally, but they can never
authorize us to set aside the true original which lies in reason and to guide
ourselves by examples.
If then there is no genuine supreme principle of morality but what must
rest simply on pure reason, independent of all experience, I think it is not
necessary even to put the question whether it is good to exhibit these
concepts in their generality (in abstracto) as they are established a priori
along with the principles belonging to them, if our knowledge is to be
distinguished from the vulgar and to be called philosophical.
In our times indeed this might perhaps be necessary; for if we collected
votes whether pure rational knowledge separated from everything empirical,
that is to say, metaphysic of morals, or whether popular practical philosophy
is to be preferred, it is easy to guess which side would preponderate.
This descending to popular notions is certainly very commendable, if the
ascent to the principles of pure reason has first taken place and been
satisfactorily accomplished. This implies that we first found ethics on
metaphysics, and then, when it is firmly established, procure a hearing for it
by giving it a popular character. But it is quite absurd to try to be popular
in the first inquiry, on which the soundness of the principles depends. It is
not only that this proceeding can never lay claim to the very rare merit of a
true philosophical popularity, since there is no art in being intelligible if
one renounces all thoroughness of insight; but also it produces a disgusting
medley of compiled observations and half-reasoned principles. Shallow pates
enjoy this because it can be used for every-day chat, but the sagacious find
in it only confusion, and being unsatisfied and unable to help themselves,
they turn away their eyes, while philosophers, who see quite well through this
delusion, are little listened to when they call men off for a time from this
pretended popularity, in order that they might be rightfully popular after
they have attained a definite insight.
We need only look at the attempts of moralists in that favourite fashion,
and we shall find at one time the special constitution of human nature
(including, however, the idea of a rational nature generally), at one time
perfection, at another happiness, here moral sense, there fear of God. a
little of this, and a little of that, in marvellous mixture, without its
occurring to them to ask whether the principles of morality are to be sought
in the knowledge of human nature at all (which we can have only from
experience); or, if this is not so, if these principles are to be found
altogether a priori, free from everything empirical, in pure rational concepts
only and nowhere else, not even in the smallest degree; then rather to adopt
the method of making this a separate inquiry, as pure practical philosophy, or
(if one may use a name so decried) as metaphysic of morals,*
to bring it by itself to completeness, and to require the public, which wishes
for popular treatment, to await the issue of this undertaking.
* Just as pure mathematics are distinguished from
applied, pure logic from applied, so if we choose we may also distinguish pure
philosophy of morals (metaphysic) from applied (viz., applied to human
nature). By this designation we are also at once reminded that moral
principles are not based on properties of human nature, but must subsist a
priori of themselves, while from such principles practical rules must be
capable of being deduced for every rational nature, and accordingly for that
of man.
Such a metaphysic of morals, completely isolated, not mixed with any
anthropology, theology, physics, or hyperphysics, and still less with occult
qualities (which we might call hypophysical), is not only an indispensable
substratum of all sound theoretical knowledge of duties, but is at the same
time a desideratum of the highest importance to the actual fulfilment of their
precepts. For the pure conception of duty, unmixed with any foreign addition
of empirical attractions, and, in a word, the conception of the moral law,
exercises on the human heart, by way of reason alone (which first becomes
aware with this that it can of itself be practical), an influence so much more
powerful than all other springs*
which may be derived from the field of experience, that, in the consciousness
of its worth, it despises the latter, and can by degrees become their master;
whereas a mixed ethics, compounded partly of motives drawn from feelings and
inclinations, and partly also of conceptions of reason, must make the mind
waver between motives which cannot be brought under any principle, which lead
to good only by mere accident and very often also to evil.
* I have a letter from the late excellent Sulzer, in
which he asks me what can be the reason that moral instruction, although
containing much that is convincing for the reason, yet accomplishes so little?
My answer was postponed in order that I might make it complete. But it is
simply this: that the teachers themselves have not got their own notions
clear, and when they endeavour to make up for this by raking up motives of
moral goodness from every quarter, trying to make their physic right strong,
they spoil it. For the commonest understanding shows that if we imagine, on
the one hand, an act of honesty done with steadfast mind, apart from every
view to advantage of any kind in this world or another, and even under the
greatest temptations of necessity or allurement, and, on the other hand, a
similar act which was affected, in however low a degree, by a foreign motive,
the former leaves far behind and eclipses the second; it elevates the soul and
inspires the wish to be able to act in like manner oneself. Even moderately
young children feel this impression, ana one should never represent duties to
them in any other light.
From what has been said, it is clear that all moral conceptions have their
seat and origin completely a priori in the reason, and that, moreover, in the
commonest reason just as truly as in that which is in the highest degree
speculative; that they cannot be obtained by abstraction from any empirical,
and therefore merely contingent, knowledge; that it is just this purity of
their origin that makes them worthy to serve as our supreme practical
principle, and that just in proportion as we add anything empirical, we
detract from their genuine influence and from the absolute value of actions;
that it is not only of the greatest necessity, in a purely speculative point
of view, but is also of the greatest practical importance, to derive these
notions and laws from pure reason, to present them pure and unmixed, and even
to determine the compass of this practical or pure rational knowledge, i.e.,
to determine the whole faculty of pure practical reason; and, in doing so, we
must not make its principles dependent on the particular nature of human
reason, though in speculative philosophy this may be permitted, or may even at
times be necessary; but since moral laws ought to hold good for every rational
creature, we must derive them from the general concept of a rational being. In
this way, although for its application to man morality has need of
anthropology, yet, in the first instance, we must treat it independently as
pure philosophy, i.e., as metaphysic, complete in itself (a thing which in
such distinct branches of science is easily done); knowing well that unless we
are in possession of this, it would not only be vain to determine the moral
element of duty in right actions for purposes of speculative criticism, but it
would be impossible to base morals on their genuine principles, even for
common practical purposes, especially of moral instruction, so as to produce
pure moral dispositions, and to engraft them on men's minds to the promotion
of the greatest possible good in the world.
But in order that in this study we may not merely advance by the natural
steps from the common moral judgement (in this case very worthy of respect) to
the philosophical, as has been already done, but also from a popular
philosophy, which goes no further than it can reach by groping with the help
of examples, to metaphysic (which does allow itself to be checked by anything
empirical and, as it must measure the whole extent of this kind of rational
knowledge, goes as far as ideal conceptions, where even examples fail us), we
must follow and clearly describe the practical faculty of reason, from the
general rules of its determination to the point where the notion of duty
springs from it.
Everything in nature works according to laws. Rational beings alone have
the faculty of acting according to the conception of laws, that is according
to principles, i.e., have a will. Since the deduction of actions from
principles requires reason, the will is nothing but practical reason. If
reason infallibly determines the will, then the actions of such a being which
are recognised as objectively necessary are subjectively necessary also, i.e.,
the will is a faculty to choose that only which reason independent of
inclination recognises as practically necessary, i.e., as good. But if reason
of itself does not sufficiently determine the will, if the latter is subject
also to subjective conditions (particular impulses) which do not always
coincide with the objective conditions; in a word, if the will does not in
itself completely accord with reason (which is actually the case with men),
then the actions which objectively are recognised as necessary are
subjectively contingent, and the determination of such a will according to
objective laws is obligation, that is to say, the relation of the objective
laws to a will that is not thoroughly good is conceived as the determination
of the will of a rational being by principles of reason, but which the will
from its nature does not of necessity follow.
The conception of an objective principle, in so far as it is obligatory for
a will, is called a command (of reason), and the formula of the command is
called an imperative.
All imperatives are expressed by the word ought [or shall], and thereby
indicate the relation of an objective law of reason to a will, which from its
subjective constitution is not necessarily determined by it (an obligation).
They say that something would be good to do or to forbear, but they say it to
a will which does not always do a thing because it is conceived to be good to
do it. That is practically good, however, which determines the will by means
of the conceptions of reason, and consequently not from subjective causes, but
objectively, that is on principles which are valid for every rational being as
such. It is distinguished from the pleasant, as that which influences the will
only by means of sensation from merely subjective causes, valid only for the
sense of this or that one, and not as a principle of reason, which holds for
every one.*
* The dependence of the desires on sensations is
called inclination, and this accordingly always indicates a want. The
dependence of a contingently determinable will on principles of reason is
called an interest. This therefore, is found only in the case of a dependent
will which does not always of itself conform to reason; in the Divine will we
cannot conceive any interest. But the human will can also take an interest in
a thing without therefore acting from interest. The former signifies the
practical interest in the action, the latter the pathological in the object of
the action. The former indicates only dependence of the will on principles of
reason in themselves; the second, dependence on principles of reason for the
sake of inclination, reason supplying only the practical rules how the
requirement of the inclination may be satisfied. In the first case the action
interests me; in the second the object of the action (because it is pleasant
to me). We have seen in the first section that in an action done from duty we
must look not to the interest in the object, but only to that in the action
itself, and in its rational principle (viz., the law).
A perfectly good will would therefore be equally subject to objective laws
(viz., laws of good), but could not be conceived as obliged thereby to act
lawfully, because of itself from its subjective constitution it can only be
determined by the conception of good. Therefore no imperatives hold for the
Divine will, or in general for a holy will; ought is here out of place,
because the volition is already of itself necessarily in unison with the law.
Therefore imperatives are only formulae to express the relation of objective
laws of all volition to the subjective imperfection of the will of this or
that rational being, e.g., the human will.
Now all imperatives command either hypothetically or categorically. The
former represent the practical necessity of a possible action as means to
something else that is willed (or at least which one might possibly will). The
categorical imperative would be that which represented an action as necessary
of itself without reference to another end, i.e., as objectively necessary.
Since every practical law represents a possible action as good and, on this
account, for a subject who is practically determinable by reason, necessary,
all imperatives are formulae determining an action which is necessary
according to the principle of a will good in some respects. If now the action
is good only as a means to something else, then the imperative is
hypothetical; if it is conceived as good in itself and consequently as being
necessarily the principle of a will which of itself conforms to reason, then
it is categorical.
Thus the imperative declares what action possible by me would be good and
presents the practical rule in relation to a will which does not forthwith
perform an action simply because it is good, whether because the subject does
not always know that it is good, or because, even if it know this, yet its
maxims might be opposed to the objective principles of practical reason.
Accordingly the hypothetical imperative only says that the action is good
for some purpose, possible or actual. In the first case it is a problematical,
in the second an assertorial practical principle. The categorical imperative
which declares an action to be objectively necessary in itself without
reference to any purpose, i.e., without any other end, is valid as an
apodeictic (practical) principle.
Whatever is possible only by the power of some rational being may also be
conceived as a possible purpose of some will; and therefore the principles of
action as regards the means necessary to attain some possible purpose are in
fact infinitely numerous. All sciences have a practical part, consisting of
problems expressing that some end is possible for us and of imperatives
directing how it may be attained. These may, therefore, be called in general
imperatives of skill. Here there is no question whether the end is rational
and good, but only what one must do in order to attain it. The precepts for
the physician to make his patient thoroughly healthy, and for a poisoner to
ensure certain death, are of equal value in this respect, that each serves to
effect its purpose perfectly. Since in early youth it cannot be known what
ends are likely to occur to us in the course of life, parents seek to have
their children taught a great many things, and provide for their skill in the
use of means for all sorts of arbitrary ends, of none of which can they
determine whether it may not perhaps hereafter be an object to their pupil,
but which it is at all events possible that he might aim at; and this anxiety
is so great that they commonly neglect to form and correct their judgement on
the value of the things which may be chosen as ends.
There is one end, however, which may be assumed to be actually such to all
rational beings (so far as imperatives apply to them, viz., as dependent
beings), and, therefore, one purpose which they not merely may have, but which
we may with certainty assume that they all actually have by a natural
necessity, and this is happiness. The hypothetical imperative which expresses
the practical necessity of an action as means to the advancement of happiness
is assertorial. We are not to present it as necessary for an uncertain and
merely possible purpose, but for a purpose which we may presuppose with
certainty and a priori in every man, because it belongs to his being. Now
skill in the choice of means to his own greatest well-being may be called
prudence,*
in the narrowest sense. And thus the imperative which refers to the choice of
means to one's own happiness, i.e., the precept of prudence, is still always
hypothetical; the action is not commanded absolutely, but only as means to
another purpose.
* The word prudence is taken in two senses: in the
one it may bear the name of knowledge of the world, in the other that of
private prudence. The former is a man's ability to influence others so as to
use them for his own purposes. The latter is the sagacity to combine all these
purposes for his own lasting benefit. This latter is properly that to which
the value even of the former is reduced, and when a man is prudent in the
former sense, but not in the latter, we might better say of him that he is
clever and cunning, but, on the whole, imprudent.
Finally, there is an imperative which commands a certain conduct
immediately, without having as its condition any other purpose to be attained
by it. This imperative is categorical. It concerns not the matter of the
action, or its intended result, but its form and the principle of which it is
itself a result; and what is essentially good in it consists in the mental
disposition, let the consequence be what it may. This imperative may be called
that of morality.
There is a marked distinction also between the volitions on these three
sorts of principles in the dissimilarity of the obligation of the will. In
order to mark this difference more clearly, I think they would be most
suitably named in their order if we said they are either rules of skill, or
counsels of prudence, or commands (laws) of morality. For it is law only that
involves the conception of an unconditional and objective necessity, which is
consequently universally valid; and commands are laws which must be obeyed,
that is, must be followed, even in opposition to inclination. Counsels,
indeed, involve necessity, but one which can only hold under a contingent
subjective condition, viz., they depend on whether this or that man reckons
this or that as part of his happiness; the categorical imperative, on the
contrary, is not limited by any condition, and as being absolutely, although
practically, necessary, may be quite properly called a command. We might also
call the first kind of imperatives technical (belonging to art), the second
pragmatic*
(to welfare), the third moral (belonging to free conduct generally, that is,
to morals).
* It seems to me that the proper signification of the
word pragmatic may be most accurately defined in this way. For sanctions are
called pragmatic which flow properly not from the law of the states as
necessary enactments, but from precaution for the general welfare. A history
is composed pragmatically when it teaches prudence, i.e., instructs the world
how it can provide for its interests better, or at least as well as, the men
of former time.
Now arises the question, how are all these imperatives possible? This
question does not seek to know how we can conceive the accomplishment of the
action which the imperative ordains, but merely how we can conceive the
obligation of the will which the imperative expresses. No special explanation
is needed to show how an imperative of skill is possible. Whoever wills the
end, wills also (so far as reason decides his conduct) the means in his power
which are indispensably necessary thereto. This proposition is, as regards the
volition, analytical; for, in willing an object as my effect, there is already
thought the causality of myself as an acting cause, that is to say, the use of
the means; and the imperative educes from the conception of volition of an end
the conception of actions necessary to this end. Synthetical propositions must
no doubt be employed in defining the means to a proposed end; but they do not
concern the principle, the act of the will, but the object and its
realization. E.g., that in order to bisect a line on an unerring principle I
must draw from its extremities two intersecting arcs; this no doubt is taught
by mathematics only in synthetical propositions; but if I know that it is only
by this process that the intended operation can be performed, then to say
that, if I fully will the operation, I also will the action required for it,
is an analytical proposition; for it is one and the same thing to conceive
something as an effect which I can produce in a certain way, and to conceive
myself as acting in this way.
If it were only equally easy to give a definite conception of happiness,
the imperatives of prudence would correspond exactly with those of skill, and
would likewise be analytical. For in this case as in that, it could be said:
"Whoever wills the end, wills also (according to the dictate of reason
necessarily) the indispensable means thereto which are in his power."
But, unfortunately, the notion of happiness is so indefinite that although
every man wishes to at. it, yet he never can say definitely and consistently
what it is that he really wishes and wills. The reason of this is that all the
elements which belong to the notion of happiness are altogether empirical,
i.e., they must be borrowed from experience, and nevertheless the idea of
happiness requires an absolute whole, a maximum of welfare in my present and
all future circumstances. Now it is impossible that the most clear-sighted and
at the same time most powerful being (supposed finite) should frame to himself
a definite conception of what he really wills in this. Does he will riches,
how much anxiety, envy, and snares might he not thereby draw upon his
shoulders? Does he will knowledge and discernment, perhaps it might prove to
be only an eye so much the sharper to show him so much the more fearfully the
evils that are now concealed from him, and that cannot be avoided, or to
impose more wants on his desires, which already give him concern enough. Would
he have long life? who guarantees to him that it would not be a long misery?
would he at least have health? how often has uneasiness of the body restrained
from excesses into which perfect health would have allowed one to fall? and so
on. In short, he is unable, on any principle, to determine with certainty what
would make him truly happy; because to do so he would need to be omniscient.
We cannot therefore act on any definite principles to secure happiness, but
only on empirical counsels, e.g. of regimen, frugality, courtesy, reserve,
etc., which experience teaches do, on the average, most promote well-being.
Hence it follows that the imperatives of prudence do not, strictly speaking,
command at all, that is, they cannot present actions objectively as
practically necessary; that they are rather to be regarded as counsels (consilia)
than precepts precepts of reason, that the problem to determine certainly and
universally what action would promote the happiness of a rational being is
completely insoluble, and consequently no imperative respecting it is possible
which should, in the strict sense, command to do what makes happy; because
happiness is not an ideal of reason but of imagination, resting solely on
empirical grounds, and it is vain to expect that these should define an action
by which one could attain the totality of a series of consequences which is
really endless. This imperative of prudence would however be an analytical
proposition if we assume that the means to happiness could be certainly
assigned; for it is distinguished from the imperative of skill only by this,
that in the latter the end is merely possible, in the former it is given; as
however both only ordain the means to that which we suppose to be willed as an
end, it follows that the imperative which ordains the willing of the means to
him who wills the end is in both cases analytical. Thus there is no difficulty
in regard to the possibility of an imperative of this kind either.
On the other hand, the question how the imperative of morality is possible,
is undoubtedly one, the only one, demanding a solution, as this is not at all
hypothetical, and the objective necessity which it presents cannot rest on any
hypothesis, as is the case with the hypothetical imperatives. Only here we
must never leave out of consideration that we cannot make out by any example,
in other words empirically, whether there is such an imperative at all, but it
is rather to be feared that all those which seem to be categorical may yet be
at bottom hypothetical. For instance, when the precept is: "Thou shalt
not promise deceitfully"; and it is assumed that the necessity of this is
not a mere counsel to avoid some other evil, so that it should mean:
"Thou shalt not make a lying promise, lest if it become known thou
shouldst destroy thy credit," but that an action of this kind must be
regarded as evil in itself, so that the imperative of the prohibition is
categorical; then we cannot show with certainty in any example that the will
was determined merely by the law, without any other spring of action, although
it may appear to be so. For it is always possible that fear of disgrace,
perhaps also obscure dread of other dangers, may have a secret influence on
the will. Who can prove by experience the non-existence of a cause when all
that experience tells us is that we do not perceive it? But in such a case the
so-called moral imperative, which as such appears to be categorical and
unconditional, would in reality be only a pragmatic precept, drawing our
attention to our own interests and merely teaching us to take these into
consideration.
We shall therefore have to investigate a priori the possibility of a
categorical imperative, as we have not in this case the advantage of its
reality being given in experience, so that [the elucidation of] its
possibility should be requisite only for its explanation, not for its
establishment. In the meantime it may be discerned beforehand that the
categorical imperative alone has the purport of a practical law; all the rest
may indeed be called principles of the will but not laws, since whatever is
only necessary for the attainment of some arbitrary purpose may be considered
as in itself contingent, and we can at any time be free from the precept if we
give up the purpose; on the contrary, the unconditional command leaves the
will no liberty to choose the opposite; consequently it alone carries with it
that necessity which we require in a law.
Secondly, in the case of this categorical imperative or law of morality,
the difficulty (of discerning its possibility) is a very profound one. It is
an a priori synthetical practical proposition;*
and as there is so much difficulty in discerning the possibility of
speculative propositions of this kind, it may readily be supposed that the
difficulty will be no less with the practical.
* I connect the act with the will without
presupposing any condition resulting from any inclination, but a priori, and
therefore necessarily (though only objectively, i.e., assuming the idea of a
reason possessing full power over all subjective motives). This is accordingly
a practical proposition which does not deduce the willing of an action by mere
analysis from another already presupposed (for we have not such a perfect
will), but connects it immediately with the conception of the will of a
rational being, as something not contained in it.
In this problem we will first inquire whether the mere conception of a
categorical imperative may not perhaps supply us also with the formula of it,
containing the proposition which alone can be a categorical imperative; for
even if we know the tenor of such an absolute command, yet how it is possible
will require further special and laborious study, which we postpone to the
last section.
When I conceive a hypothetical imperative, in general I do not know
beforehand what it will contain until I am given the condition. But when I
conceive a categorical imperative, I know at once what it contains. For as the
imperative contains besides the law only the necessity that the maxims*
shall conform to this law, while the law contains no conditions restricting
it, there remains nothing but the general statement that the maxim of the
action should conform to a universal law, and it is this conformity alone that
the imperative properly represents as necessary.
* A maxim is a subjective principle of action, and
must be distinguished from the objective principle, namely, practical law. The
former contains the practical rule set by reason according to the conditions
of the subject (often its ignorance or its inclinations), so that it is the
principle on which the subject acts; but the law is the objective principle
valid for every rational being, and is the principle on which it ought to act
that is an imperative.
There is therefore but one categorical imperative, namely, this: Act only
on that maxim whereby thou canst at the same time will that it should become a
universal law.
Now if all imperatives of duty can be deduced from this one imperative as
from their principle, then, although it should remain undecided what is called
duty is not merely a vain notion, yet at least we shall be able to show what
we understand by it and what this notion means.
Since the universality of the law according to which effects are produced
constitutes what is properly called nature in the most general sense (as to
form), that is the existence of things so far as it is determined by general
laws, the imperative of duty may be expressed thus: Act as if the maxim of thy
action were to become by thy will a universal law of nature.
We will now enumerate a few duties, adopting the usual division of them
into duties to ourselves and ourselves and to others, and into perfect and
imperfect duties.*
* It must be noted here that I reserve the division
of duties for a future metaphysic of morals; so that I give it here only as an
arbitrary one (in order to arrange my examples). For the rest, I understand by
a perfect duty one that admits no exception in favour of inclination and then
I have not merely external but also internal perfect duties. This is contrary
to the use of the word adopted in the schools; but I do not intend to justify
there, as it is all one for my purpose whether it is admitted or not.
1. A man reduced to despair by a series of misfortunes feels wearied of
life, but is still so far in possession of his reason that he can ask himself
whether it would not be contrary to his duty to himself to take his own life.
Now he inquires whether the maxim of his action could become a universal law
of nature. His maxim is: "From self-love I adopt it as a principle to
shorten my life when its longer duration is likely to bring more evil than
satisfaction." It is asked then simply whether this principle founded on
self-love can become a universal law of nature. Now we see at once that a
system of nature of which it should be a law to destroy life by means of the
very feeling whose special nature it is to impel to the improvement of life
would contradict itself and, therefore, could not exist as a system of nature;
hence that maxim cannot possibly exist as a universal law of nature and,
consequently, would be wholly inconsistent with the supreme principle of all
duty.
2. Another finds himself forced by necessity to borrow money. He knows that
he will not be able to repay it, but sees also that nothing will be lent to
him unless he promises stoutly to repay it in a definite time. He desires to
make this promise, but he has still so much conscience as to ask himself:
"Is it not unlawful and inconsistent with duty to get out of a difficulty
in this way?" Suppose however that he resolves to do so: then the maxim
of his action would be expressed thus: "When I think myself in want of
money, I will borrow money and promise to repay it, although I know that I
never can do so." Now this principle of self-love or of one's own
advantage may perhaps be consistent with my whole future welfare; but the
question now is, "Is it right?" I change then the suggestion of
self-love into a universal law, and state the question thus: "How would
it be if my maxim were a universal law?" Then I see at once that it could
never hold as a universal law of nature, but would necessarily contradict
itself. For supposing it to be a universal law that everyone when he thinks
himself in a difficulty should be able to promise whatever he pleases, with
the purpose of not keeping his promise, the promise itself would become
impossible, as well as the end that one might have in view in it, since no one
would consider that anything was promised to him, but would ridicule all such
statements as vain pretences.
3. A third finds in himself a talent which with the help of some culture
might make him a useful man in many respects. But he finds himself in
comfortable circumstances and prefers to indulge in pleasure rather than to
take pains in enlarging and improving his happy natural capacities. He asks,
however, whether his maxim of neglect of his natural gifts, besides agreeing
with his inclination to indulgence, agrees also with what is called duty. He
sees then that a system of nature could indeed subsist with such a universal
law although men (like the South Sea islanders) should let their talents rest
and resolve to devote their lives merely to idleness, amusement, and
propagation of their species — in a word, to enjoyment; but he cannot
possibly will that this should be a universal law of nature, or be implanted
in us as such by a natural instinct. For, as a rational being, he necessarily
wills that his faculties be developed, since they serve him and have been
given him, for all sorts of possible purposes.
4. A fourth, who is in prosperity, while he sees that others have to
contend with great wretchedness and that he could help them, thinks:
"What concern is it of mine? Let everyone be as happy as Heaven pleases,
or as be can make himself; I will take nothing from him nor even envy him,
only I do not wish to contribute anything to his welfare or to his assistance
in distress!" Now no doubt if such a mode of thinking were a universal
law, the human race might very well subsist and doubtless even better than in
a state in which everyone talks of sympathy and good-will, or even takes care
occasionally to put it into practice, but, on the other side, also cheats when
he can, betrays the rights of men, or otherwise violates them. But although it
is possible that a universal law of nature might exist in accordance with that
maxim, it is impossible to will that such a principle should have the
universal validity of a law of nature. For a will which resolved this would
contradict itself, inasmuch as many cases might occur in which one would have
need of the love and sympathy of others, and in which, by such a law of
nature, sprung from his own will, he would deprive himself of all hope of the
aid he desires.
These are a few of the many actual duties, or at least what we regard as
such, which obviously fall into two classes on the one principle that we have
laid down. We must be able to will that a maxim of our action should be a
universal law. This is the canon of the moral appreciation of the action
generally. Some actions are of such a character that their maxim cannot
without contradiction be even conceived as a universal law of nature, far from
it being possible that we should will that it should be so. In others this
intrinsic impossibility is not found, but still it is impossible to will that
their maxim should be raised to the universality of a law of nature, since
such a will would contradict itself It is easily seen that the former violate
strict or rigorous (inflexible) duty; the latter only laxer (meritorious)
duty. Thus it has been completely shown how all duties depend as regards the
nature of the obligation (not the object of the action) on the same principle.
If now we attend to ourselves on occasion of any transgression of duty, we
shall find that we in fact do not will that our maxim should be a universal
law, for that is impossible for us; on the contrary, we will that the opposite
should remain a universal law, only we assume the liberty of making an
exception in our own favour or (just for this time only) in favour of our
inclination. Consequently if we considered all cases from one and the same
point of view, namely, that of reason, we should find a contradiction in our
own will, namely, that a certain principle should be objectively necessary as
a universal law, and yet subjectively should not be universal, but admit of
exceptions. As however we at one moment regard our action from the point of
view of a will wholly conformed to reason, and then again look at the same
action from the point of view of a will affected by inclination, there is not
really any contradiction, but an antagonism of inclination to the precept of
reason, whereby the universality of the principle is changed into a mere
generality, so that the practical principle of reason shall meet the maxim
half way. Now, although this cannot be justified in our own impartial
judgement, yet it proves that we do really recognise the validity of the
categorical imperative and (with all respect for it) only allow ourselves a
few exceptions, which we think unimportant and forced from us.
We have thus established at least this much, that if duty is a conception
which is to have any import and real legislative authority for our actions, it
can only be expressed in categorical and not at all in hypothetical
imperatives. We have also, which is of great importance, exhibited clearly and
definitely for every practical application the content of the categorical
imperative, which must contain the principle of all duty if there is such a
thing at all. We have not yet, however, advanced so far as to prove a priori
that there actually is such an imperative, that there is a practical law which
commands absolutely of itself and without any other impulse, and that the
following of this law is duty.
With the view of attaining to this, it is of extreme importance to remember
that we must not allow ourselves to think of deducing the reality of this
principle from the particular attributes of human nature. For duty is to be a
practical, unconditional necessity of action; it must therefore hold for all
rational beings (to whom an imperative can apply at all), and for this reason
only be also a law for all human wills. On the contrary, whatever is deduced
from the particular natural characteristics of humanity, from certain feelings
and propensions, nay, even, if possible, from any particular tendency proper
to human reason, and which need not necessarily hold for the will of every
rational being; this may indeed supply us with a maxim, but not with a law;
with a subjective principle on which we may have a propension and inclination
to act, but not with an objective principle on which we should be enjoined to
act, even though all our propensions, inclinations, and natural dispositions
were opposed to it. In fact, the sublimity and intrinsic dignity of the
command in duty are so much the more evident, the less the subjective impulses
favour it and the more they oppose it, without being able in the slightest
degree to weaken the obligation of the law or to diminish its validity.
Here then we see philosophy brought to a critical position, since it has to
be firmly fixed, notwithstanding that it has nothing to support it in heaven
or earth. Here it must show its purity as absolute director of its own laws,
not the herald of those which are whispered to it by an implanted sense or who
knows what tutelary nature. Although these may be better than nothing, yet
they can never afford principles dictated by reason, which must have their
source wholly a priori and thence their commanding authority, expecting
everything from the supremacy of the law and the due respect for it, nothing
from inclination, or else condemning the man to self-contempt and inward
abhorrence.
Thus every empirical element is not only quite incapable of being an aid to
the principle of morality, but is even highly prejudicial to the purity of
morals, for the proper and inestimable worth of an absolutely good will
consists just in this, that the principle of action is free from all influence
of contingent grounds, which alone experience can furnish. We cannot too much
or too often repeat our warning against this lax and even mean habit of
thought which seeks for its principle amongst empirical motives and laws; for
human reason in its weariness is glad to rest on this pillow, and in a dream
of sweet illusions (in which, instead of Juno, it embraces a cloud) it
substitutes for morality a bastard patched up from limbs of various
derivation, which looks like anything one chooses to see in it, only not like
virtue to one who has once beheld her in her true form.*
* To behold virtue in her proper form is nothing
else but to contemplate morality stripped of all admixture of sensible things
and of every spurious ornament of reward or self-love. How much she then
eclipses everything else that appears charming to the affections, every one
may readily perceive with the least exertion of his reason, if it be not
wholly spoiled for abstraction.
The question then is this: "Is it a necessary law for all rational
beings that they should always judge of their actions by maxims of which they
can themselves will that they should serve as universal laws?" If it is
so, then it must be connected (altogether a priori) with the very conception
of the will of a rational being generally. But in order to discover this
connexion we must, however reluctantly, take a step into metaphysic, although
into a domain of it which is distinct from speculative philosophy, namely, the
metaphysic of morals. In a practical philosophy, where it is not the reasons
of what happens that we have to ascertain, but the laws of what ought to
happen, even although it never does, i.e., objective practical laws, there it
is not necessary to inquire into the reasons why anything pleases or
displeases, how the pleasure of mere sensation differs from taste, and whether
the latter is distinct from a general satisfaction of reason; on what the
feeling of pleasure or pain rests, and how from it desires and inclinations
arise, and from these again maxims by the co-operation of reason: for all this
belongs to an empirical psychology, which would constitute the second part of
physics, if we regard physics as the philosophy of nature, so far as it is
based on empirical laws. But here we are concerned with objective practical
laws and, consequently, with the relation of the will to itself so far as it
is determined by reason alone, in which case whatever has reference to
anything empirical is necessarily excluded; since if reason of itself alone
determines the conduct (and it is the possibility of this that we are now
investigating), it must necessarily do so a priori.
The will is conceived as a faculty of determining oneself to action in
accordance with the conception of certain laws. And such a faculty can be
found only in rational beings. Now that which serves the will as the objective
ground of its self-determination is the end, and, if this is assigned by
reason alone, it must hold for all rational beings. On the other hand, that
which merely contains the ground of possibility of the action of which the
effect is the end, this is called the means. The subjective ground of the
desire is the spring, the objective ground of the volition is the motive;
hence the distinction between subjective ends which rest on springs, and
objective ends which depend on motives valid for every rational being.
Practical principles are formal when they abstract from all subjective ends;
they are material when they assume these, and therefore particular springs of
action. The ends which a rational being proposes to himself at pleasure as
effects of his actions (material ends) are all only relative, for it is only
their relation to the particular desires of the subject that gives them their
worth, which therefore cannot furnish principles universal and necessary for
all rational beings and for every volition, that is to say practical laws.
Hence all these relative ends can give rise only to hypothetical imperatives.
Supposing, however, that there were something whose existence has in itself
an absolute worth, something which, being an end in itself, could be a source
of definite laws; then in this and this alone would lie the source of a
possible categorical imperative, i.e., a practical law.
Now I say: man and generally any rational being exists as an end in
himself, not merely as a means to be arbitrarily used by this or that will,
but in all his actions, whether they concern himself or other rational beings,
must be always regarded at the same time as an end. All objects of the
inclinations have only a conditional worth, for if the inclinations and the
wants founded on them did not exist, then their object would be without value.
But the inclinations, themselves being sources of want, are so far from having
an absolute worth for which they should be desired that on the contrary it
must be the universal wish of every rational being to be wholly free from
them. Thus the worth of any object which is to be acquired by our action is
always conditional. Beings whose existence depends not on our will but on
nature's, have nevertheless, if they are irrational beings, only a relative
value as means, and are therefore called things; rational beings, on the
contrary, are called persons, because their very nature points them out as
ends in themselves, that is as something which must not be used merely as
means, and so far therefore restricts freedom of action (and is an object of
respect). These, therefore, are not merely subjective ends whose existence has
a worth for us as an effect of our action, but objective ends, that is, things
whose existence is an end in itself; an end moreover for which no other can be
substituted, which they should subserve merely as means, for otherwise nothing
whatever would possess absolute worth; but if all worth were conditioned and
therefore contingent, then there would be no supreme practical principle of
reason whatever.
If then there is a supreme practical principle or, in respect of the human
will, a categorical imperative, it must be one which, being drawn from the
conception of that which is necessarily an end for everyone because it is an
end in itself, constitutes an objective principle of will, and can therefore
serve as a universal practical law. The foundation of this principle is:
rational nature exists as an end in itself. Man necessarily conceives his own
existence as being so; so far then this is a subjective principle of human
actions. But every other rational being regards its existence similarly, just
on the same rational principle that holds for me:*
so that it is at the same time an objective principle, from which as a supreme
practical law all laws of the will must be capable of being deduced.
Accordingly the practical imperative will be as follows: So act as to treat
humanity, whether in thine own person or in that of any other, in every case
as an end withal, never as means only. We will now inquire whether this can be
practically carried out.
* This proposition is here stated as a postulate.
The ground of it will be found in the concluding section.
To abide by the previous examples:
Firstly, under the head of necessary duty to oneself: He who contemplates
suicide should ask himself whether his action can be consistent with the idea
of humanity as an end in itself. If he destroys himself in order to escape
from painful circumstances, he uses a person merely as a mean to maintain a
tolerable condition up to the end of life. But a man is not a thing, that is
to say, something which can be used merely as means, but must in all his
actions be always considered as an end in himself. I cannot, therefore,
dispose in any way of a man in my own person so as to mutilate him, to damage
or kill him. (It belongs to ethics proper to define this principle more
precisely, so as to avoid all misunderstanding, e. g., as to the amputation of
the limbs in order to preserve myself, as to exposing my life to danger with a
view to preserve it, etc. This question is therefore omitted here.)
Secondly, as regards necessary duties, or those of strict obligation,
towards others: He who is thinking of making a lying promise to others will
see at once that he would be using another man merely as a mean, without the
latter containing at the same time the end in himself. For he whom I propose
by such a promise to use for my own purposes cannot possibly assent to my mode
of acting towards him and, therefore, cannot himself contain the end of this
action. This violation of the principle of humanity in other men is more
obvious if we take in examples of attacks on the freedom and property of
others. For then it is clear that he who transgresses the rights of men
intends to use the person of others merely as a means, without considering
that as rational beings they ought always to be esteemed also as ends, that
is, as beings who must be capable of containing in themselves the end of the
very same action.*
* Let it not be thought that the common "quod
tibi non vis fieri, etc." could serve here as the rule or principle. For
it is only a deduction from the former, though with several limitations; it
cannot be a universal law, for it does not contain the principle of duties to
oneself, nor of the duties of benevolence to others (for many a one would
gladly consent that others should not benefit him, provided only that he might
be excused from showing benevolence to them), nor finally that of duties of
strict obligation to one another, for on this principle the criminal might
argue against the judge who punishes him, and so on.
Thirdly, as regards contingent (meritorious) duties to oneself: It is not
enough that the action does not violate humanity in our own person as an end
in itself, it must also harmonize with it. Now there are in humanity
capacities of greater perfection, which belong to the end that nature has in
view in regard to humanity in ourselves as the subject: to neglect these might
perhaps be consistent with the maintenance of humanity as an end in itself,
but not with the advancement of this end.
Fourthly, as regards meritorious duties towards others: The natural end
which all men have is their own happiness. Now humanity might indeed subsist,
although no one should contribute anything to the happiness of others,
provided he did not intentionally withdraw anything from it; but after all
this would only harmonize negatively not positively with humanity as an end in
itself, if every one does not also endeavour, as far as in him lies, to
forward the ends of others. For the ends of any subject which is an end in
himself ought as far as possible to be my ends also, if that conception is to
have its full effect with me.
This principle, that humanity and generally every rational nature is an end
in itself (which is the supreme limiting condition of every man's freedom of
action), is not borrowed from experience, firstly, because it is universal,
applying as it does to all rational beings whatever, and experience is not
capable of determining anything about them; secondly, because it does not
present humanity as an end to men (subjectively), that is as an object which
men do of themselves actually adopt as an end; but as an objective end, which
must as a law constitute the supreme limiting condition of all our subjective
ends, let them be what we will; it must therefore spring from pure reason. In
fact the objective principle of all practical legislation lies (according to
the first principle) in the rule and its form of universality which makes it
capable of being a law (say, e. g., a law of nature); but the subjective
principle is in the end; now by the second principle the subject of all ends
is each rational being, inasmuch as it is an end in itself. Hence follows the
third practical principle of the will, which is the ultimate condition of its
harmony with universal practical reason, viz.: the idea of the will of every
rational being as a universally legislative will.
On this principle all maxims are rejected which are inconsistent with the
will being itself universal legislator. Thus the will is not subject simply to
the law, but so subject that it must be regarded as itself giving the law and,
on this ground only, subject to the law (of which it can regard itself as the
author).
In the previous imperatives, namely, that based on the conception of the
conformity of actions to general laws, as in a physical system of nature, and
that based on the universal prerogative of rational beings as ends in
themselves — these imperatives, just because they were conceived as
categorical, excluded from any share in their authority all admixture of any
interest as a spring of action; they were, however, only assumed to be
categorical, because such an assumption was necessary to explain the
conception of duty. But we could not prove independently that there are
practical propositions which command categorically, nor can it be proved in
this section; one thing, however, could be done, namely, to indicate in the
imperative itself, by some determinate expression, that in the case of
volition from duty all interest is renounced, which is the specific criterion
of categorical as distinguished from hypothetical imperatives. This is done in
the present (third) formula of the principle, namely, in the idea of the will
of every rational being as a universally legislating will.
For although a will which is subject to laws may be attached to this law by
means of an interest, yet a will which is itself a supreme lawgiver so far as
it is such cannot possibly depend on any interest, since a will so dependent
would itself still need another law restricting the interest of its self-love
by the condition that it should be valid as universal law.
Thus the principle that every human will is a will which in all its maxims
gives universal laws,*
provided it be otherwise justified, would be very well adapted to be the
categorical imperative, in this respect, namely, that just because of the idea
of universal legislation it is not based on interest, and therefore it alone
among all possible imperatives can be unconditional. Or still better,
converting the proposition, if there is a categorical imperative (i.e., a law
for the will of every rational being), it can only command that everything be
done from maxims of one's will regarded as a will which could at the same time
will that it should itself give universal laws, for in that case only the
practical principle and the imperative which it obeys are unconditional, since
they cannot be based on any interest.
* I may be excused from adducing examples to
elucidate this principle, as those which have already been used to elucidate
the categorical imperative and its formula would all serve for the like
purpose here.
Looking back now on all previous attempts to discover the principle of
morality, we need not wonder why they all failed. It was seen that man was
bound to laws by duty, but it was not observed that the laws to which he is
subject are only those of his own giving, though at the same time they are
universal, and that he is only bound to act in conformity with his own will; a
will, however, which is designed by nature to give universal laws. For when
one has conceived man only as subject to a law (no matter what), then this law
required some interest, either by way of attraction or constraint, since it
did not originate as a law from his own will, but this will was according to a
law obliged by something else to act in a certain manner. Now by this
necessary consequence all the labour spent in finding a supreme principle of
duty was irrevocably lost. For men never elicited duty, but only a necessity
of acting from a certain interest. Whether this interest was private or
otherwise, in any case the imperative must be conditional and could not by any
means be capable of being a moral command. I will therefore call this the
principle of autonomy of the will, in contrast with every other which I
accordingly reckon as heteronomy.
The conception of the will of every rational being as one which must
consider itself as giving in all the maxims of its will universal laws, so as
to judge itself and its actions from this point of viewthis conception leads
to another which depends on it and is very fruitful, namely that of a kingdom
of ends.
By a kingdom I understand the union of different rational beings in a
system by common laws. Now since it is by laws that ends are determined as
regards their universal validity, hence, if we abstract from the personal
differences of rational beings and likewise from all the content of their
private ends, we shall be able to conceive all ends combined in a systematic
whole (including both rational beings as ends in themselves, and also the
special ends which each may propose to himself), that is to say, we can
conceive a kingdom of ends, which on the preceding principles is possible.
For all rational beings come under the law that each of them must treat
itself and all others never merely as means, but in every case at the same
time as ends in themselves. Hence results a systematic union of rational being
by common objective laws, i.e., a kingdom which may be called a kingdom of
ends, since what these laws have in view is just the relation of these beings
to one another as ends and means. It is certainly only an ideal.
A rational being belongs as a member to the kingdom of ends when, although
giving universal laws in it, he is also himself subject to these laws. He
belongs to it as sovereign when, while giving laws, he is not subject to the
will of any other.
A rational being must always regard himself as giving laws either as member
or as sovereign in a kingdom of ends which is rendered possible by the freedom
of will. He cannot, however, maintain the latter position merely by the maxims
of his will, but only in case he is a completely independent being without
wants and with unrestricted power adequate to his will.
Morality consists then in the reference of all action to the legislation
which alone can render a kingdom of ends possible. This legislation must be
capable of existing in every rational being and of emanating from his will, so
that the principle of this will is never to act on any maxim which could not
without contradiction be also a universal law and, accordingly, always so to
act that the will could at the same time regard itself as giving in its maxims
universal laws. If now the maxims of rational beings are not by their own
nature coincident with this objective principle, then the necessity of acting
on it is called practical necessitation, i.e., duty. Duty does not apply to
the sovereign in the kingdom of ends, but it does to every member of it and to
all in the same degree.
The practical necessity of acting on this principle, i.e., duty, does not
rest at all on feelings, impulses, or inclinations, but solely on the relation
of rational beings to one another, a relation in which the will of a rational
being must always be regarded as legislative, since otherwise it could not be
conceived as an end in itself. Reason then refers every maxim of the will,
regarding it as legislating universally, to every other will and also to every
action towards oneself; and this not on account of any other practical motive
or any future advantage, but from the idea of the dignity of a rational being,
obeying no law but that which he himself also gives.
In the kingdom of ends everything has either value or dignity. Whatever has
a value can be replaced by something else which is equivalent; whatever, on
the other hand, is above all value, and therefore admits of no equivalent, has
a dignity.
Whatever has reference to the general inclinations and wants of mankind has
a market value; whatever, without presupposing a want, corresponds to a
certain taste, that is to a satisfaction in the mere purposeless play of our
faculties, has a fancy value; but that which constitutes the condition under
which alone anything can be an end in itself, this has not merely a relative
worth, i.e., value, but an intrinsic worth, that is, dignity.
Now morality is the condition under which alone a rational being can be an
end in himself, since by this alone is it possible that he should be a
legislating member in the kingdom of ends. Thus morality, and humanity as
capable of it, is that which alone has dignity. Skill and diligence in labour
have a market value; wit, lively imagination, and humour, have fancy value; on
the other hand, fidelity to promises, benevolence from principle (not from
instinct), have an intrinsic worth. Neither nature nor art contains anything
which in default of these it could put in their place, for their worth
consists not in the effects which spring from them, not in the use and
advantage which they secure, but in the disposition of mind, that is, the
maxims of the will which are ready to manifest themselves in such actions,
even though they should not have the desired effect. These actions also need
no recommendation from any subjective taste or sentiment, that they may be
looked on with immediate favour and satisfaction: they need no immediate
propension or feeling for them; they exhibit the will that performs them as an
object of an immediate respect, and nothing but reason is required to impose
them on the will; not to flatter it into them, which, in the case of duties,
would be a contradiction. This estimation therefore shows that the worth of
such a disposition is dignity, and places it infinitely above all value, with
which it cannot for a moment be brought into comparison or competition without
as it were violating its sanctity.
What then is it which justifies virtue or the morally good disposition, in
making such lofty claims? It is nothing less than the privilege it secures to
the rational being of participating in the giving of universal laws, by which
it qualifies him to be a member of a possible kingdom of ends, a privilege to
which he was already destined by his own nature as being an end in himself
and, on that account, legislating in the kingdom of ends; free as regards all
laws of physical nature, and obeying those only which he himself gives, and by
which his maxims can belong to a system of universal law, to which at the same
time he submits himself. For nothing has any worth except what the law assigns
it. Now the legislation itself which assigns the worth of everything must for
that very reason possess dignity, that is an unconditional incomparable worth;
and the word respect alone supplies a becoming expression for the esteem which
a rational being must have for it. Autonomy then is the basis of the dignity
of human and of every rational nature.
The three modes of presenting the principle of morality that have been
adduced are at bottom only so many formulae of the very same law, and each of
itself involves the other two. There is, however, a difference in them, but it
is rather subjectively than objectively practical, intended namely to bring an
idea of the reason nearer to intuition (by means of a certain analogy) and
thereby nearer to feeling. All maxims, in fact, have:
1. A form, consisting in universality; and in this view the formula of the
moral imperative is expressed thus, that the maxims must be so chosen as if
they were to serve as universal laws of nature.
2. A matter, namely, an end, and here the formula says that the rational
being, as it is an end by its own nature and therefore an end in itself, must
in every maxim serve as the condition limiting all merely relative and
arbitrary ends.
3. A complete characterization of all maxims by means of that formula,
namely, that all maxims ought by their own legislation to harmonize with a
possible kingdom of ends as with a kingdom of nature.*
There is a progress here in the order of the categories of unity of the form
of the will (its universality), plurality of the matter (the objects, i.e.,
the ends), and totality of the system of these. In forming our moral judgement
of actions, it is better to proceed always on the strict method and start from
the general formula of the categorical imperative: Act according to a maxim
which can at the same time make itself a universal law. If, however, we wish
to gain an entrance for the moral law, it is very useful to bring one and the
same action under the three specified conceptions, and thereby as far as
possible to bring it nearer to intuition.
* Teleology considers nature as a kingdom of ends;
ethics regards a possible kingdom of ends as a kingdom nature. In the first
case, the kingdom of ends is a theoretical idea, adopted to explain what
actually is. In the latter it is a practical idea, adopted to bring about that
which is not yet, but which can be realized by our conduct, namely, if it
conforms to this idea.
We can now end where we started at the beginning, namely, with the
conception of a will unconditionally good. That will is absolutely good which
cannot be evil — in other words, whose maxim, if made a universal law, could
never contradict itself. This principle, then, is its supreme law: "Act
always on such a maxim as thou canst at the same time will to be a universal
law"; this is the sole condition under which a will can never contradict
itself; and such an imperative is categorical. Since the validity of the will
as a universal law for possible actions is analogous to the universal
connexion of the existence of things by general laws, which is the formal
notion of nature in general, the categorical imperative can also be expressed
thus: Act on maxims which can at the same time have for their object
themselves as universal laws of nature. Such then is the formula of an
absolutely good will.
Rational nature is distinguished from the rest of nature by this, that it
sets before itself an end. This end would be the matter of every good will.
But since in the idea of a will that is absolutely good without being limited
by any condition (of attaining this or that end) we must abstract wholly from
every end to be effected (since this would make every will only relatively
good), it follows that in this case the end must be conceived, not as an end
to be effected, but as an independently existing end. Consequently it is
conceived only negatively, i.e., as that which we must never act against and
which, therefore, must never be regarded merely as means, but must in every
volition be esteemed as an end likewise. Now this end can be nothing but the
subject of all possible ends, since this is also the subject of a possible
absolutely good will; for such a will cannot without contradiction be
postponed to any other object. The principle: "So act in regard to every
rational being (thyself and others), that he may always have place in thy
maxim as an end in himself," is accordingly essentially identical with
this other: "Act upon a maxim which, at the same time, involves its own
universal validity for every rational being." For that in using means for
every end I should limit my maxim by the condition of its holding good as a
law for every subject, this comes to the same thing as that the fundamental
principle of all maxims of action must be that the subject of all ends, i.e.,
the rational being himself, be never employed merely as means, but as the
supreme condition restricting the use of all means, that is in every case as
an end likewise.
It follows incontestably that, to whatever laws any rational being may be
subject, he being an end in himself must be able to regard himself as also
legislating universally in respect of these same laws, since it is just this
fitness of his maxims for universal legislation that distinguishes him as an
end in himself; also it follows that this implies his dignity (prerogative)
above all mere physical beings, that he must always take his maxims from the
point of view which regards himself and, likewise, every other rational being
as law-giving beings (on which account they are called persons). In this way a
world of rational beings (mundus intelligibilis) is possible as a kingdom of
ends, and this by virtue of the legislation proper to all persons as members.
Therefore every rational being must so act as if he were by his maxims in
every case a legislating member in the universal kingdom of ends. The formal
principle of these maxims is: "So act as if thy maxim were to serve
likewise as the universal law (of all rational beings)." A kingdom of
ends is thus only possible on the analogy of a kingdom of nature, the former
however only by maxims, that is self-imposed rules, the latter only by the
laws of efficient causes acting under necessitation from without.
Nevertheless, although the system of nature is looked upon as a machine, yet
so far as it has reference to rational beings as its ends, it is given on this
account the name of a kingdom of nature. Now such a kingdom of ends would be
actually realized by means of maxims conforming to the canon which the
categorical imperative prescribes to all rational beings, if they were
universally followed. But although a rational being, even if he punctually
follows this maxim himself, cannot reckon upon all others being therefore true
to the same, nor expect that the kingdom of nature and its orderly
arrangements shall be in harmony with him as a fitting member, so as to form a
kingdom of ends to which he himself contributes, that is to say, that it shall
favour his expectation of happiness, still that law: "Act according to
the maxims of a member of a merely possible kingdom of ends legislating in it
universally," remains in its full force, inasmuch as it commands
categorically. And it is just in this that the paradox lies; that the mere
dignity of man as a rational creature, without any other end or advantage to
be attained thereby, in other words, respect for a mere idea, should yet serve
as an inflexible precept of the will, and that it is precisely in this
independence of the maxim on all such springs of action that its sublimity
consists; and it is this that makes every rational subject worthy to be a
legislative member in the kingdom of ends: for otherwise he would have to be
conceived only as subject to the physical law of his wants. And although we
should suppose the kingdom of nature and the kingdom of ends to be united
under one sovereign, so that the latter kingdom thereby ceased to be a mere
idea and acquired true reality, then it would no doubt gain the accession of a
strong spring, but by no means any increase of its intrinsic worth. For this
sole absolute lawgiver must, notwithstanding this, be always conceived as
estimating the worth of rational beings only by their disinterested behaviour,
as prescribed to themselves from that idea [the dignity of man] alone. The
essence of things is not altered by their external relations, and that which,
abstracting from these, alone constitutes the absolute worth of man, is also
that by which he must be judged, whoever the judge may be, and even by the
Supreme Being. Morality, then, is the relation of actions to the relation of
actions will, that is, to the autonomy of potential universal legislation by
its maxims. An action that is consistent with the autonomy of the will is
permitted; one that does not agree therewith is forbidden. A will whose maxims
necessarily coincide with the laws of autonomy is a holy will, good
absolutely. The dependence of a will not absolutely good on the principle of
autonomy (moral necessitation) is obligation. This, then, cannot be applied to
a holy being. The objective necessity of actions from obligation is called
duty.
From what has just been said, it is easy to see how it happens that,
although the conception of duty implies subjection to the law, we yet ascribe
a certain dignity and sublimity to the person who fulfils all his duties.
There is not, indeed, any sublimity in him, so far as he is subject to the
moral law; but inasmuch as in regard to that very law he is likewise a
legislator, and on that account alone subject to it, he has sublimity. We have
also shown above that neither fear nor inclination, but simply respect for the
law, is the spring which can give actions a moral worth. Our own will, so far
as we suppose it to act only under the condition that its maxims are
potentially universal laws, this ideal will which is possible to us is the
proper object of respect; and the dignity of humanity consists just in this
capacity of being universally legislative, though with the condition that it
is itself subject to this same legislation.
The Autonomy of the Will as the Supreme Principle of Morality
Autonomy of the will is that property of it by which it is a law to itself
(independently of any property of the objects of volition). The principle of
autonomy then is: "Always so to choose that the same volition shall
comprehend the maxims of our choice as a universal law." We cannot prove
that this practical rule is an imperative, i.e., that the will of every
rational being is necessarily bound to it as a condition, by a mere analysis
of the conceptions which occur in it, since it is a synthetical proposition;
we must advance beyond the cognition of the objects to a critical examination
of the subject, that is, of the pure practical reason, for this synthetic
proposition which commands apodeictically must be capable of being cognized
wholly a priori. This matter, however, does not belong to the present section.
But that the principle of autonomy in question is the sole principle of morals
can be readily shown by mere analysis of the conceptions of morality. For by
this analysis we find that its principle must be a categorical imperative and
that what this commands is neither more nor less than this very autonomy.
Heteronomy of the Will as the Source of all spurious Principles of
Morality
If the will seeks the law which is to determine it anywhere else than in
the fitness of its maxims to be universal laws of its own dictation,
consequently if it goes out of itself and seeks this law in the character of
any of its objects, there always results heteronomy. The will in that case
does not give itself the law, but it is given by the object through its
relation to the will. This relation, whether it rests on inclination or on
conceptions of reason, only admits of hypothetical imperatives: "I ought
to do something because I wish for something else." On the contrary, the
moral, and therefore categorical, imperative says: "I ought to do so and
so, even though I should not wish for anything else." E.g., the former
says: "I ought not to lie, if I would retain my reputation"; the
latter says: "I ought not to lie, although it should not bring me the
least discredit." The latter therefore must so far abstract from all
objects that they shall have no influence on the will, in order that practical
reason (will) may not be restricted to administering an interest not belonging
to it, but may simply show its own commanding authority as the supreme
legislation. Thus, e.g., I ought to endeavour to promote the happiness of
others, not as if its realization involved any concern of mine (whether by
immediate inclination or by any satisfaction indirectly gained through
reason), but simply because a maxim which excludes it cannot be comprehended
as a universal law in one and the same volition.
Classification of all Principles of Morality which can be founded on the
Conception of Heteronomy
Here as elsewhere human reason in its pure use, so long as it was not
critically examined, has first tried all possible wrong ways before it
succeeded in finding the one true way.
All principles which can be taken from this point of view are either
empirical or rational. The former, drawn from the principle of happiness, are
built on physical or moral feelings; the latter, drawn from the principle of
perfection, are built either on the rational conception of perfection as a
possible effect, or on that of an independent perfection (the will of God) as
the determining cause of our will.
Empirical principles are wholly incapable of serving as a foundation for
moral laws. For the universality with which these should hold for all rational
beings without distinction, the unconditional practical necessity which is
thereby imposed on them, is lost when their foundation is taken from the
particular constitution of human nature, or the accidental circumstances in
which it is placed. The principle of private happiness, however, is the most
objectionable, not merely because it is false, and experience contradicts the
supposition that prosperity is always proportioned to good conduct, nor yet
merely because it contributes nothing to the establishment of morality —
since it is quite a different thing to make a prosperous man and a good man,
or to make one prudent and sharp-sighted for his own interests and to make him
virtuous — but because the springs it provides for morality are such as
rather undermine it and destroy its sublimity, since they put the motives to
virtue and to vice in the same class and only teach us to make a better
calculation, the specific difference between virtue and vice being entirely
extinguished. On the other hand, as to moral feeling, this supposed special
sense,*
the appeal to it is indeed superficial when those who cannot think believe
that feeling will help them out, even in what concerns general laws: and
besides, feelings, which naturally differ infinitely in degree, cannot furnish
a uniform standard of good and evil, nor has anyone a right to form judgements
for others by his own feelings: nevertheless this moral feeling is nearer to
morality and its dignity in this respect, that it pays virtue the honour of
ascribing to her immediately the satisfaction and esteem we have for her and
does not, as it were, tell her to her face that we are not attached to her by
her beauty but by profit.
* I class the principle of moral feeling under that
of happiness, because every empirical interest promises to contribute to our
well-being by the agreeableness that a thing affords, whether it be
immediately and without a view to profit, or whether profit be regarded. We
must likewise, with Hutcheson, class the principle of sympathy with the
happiness of others under his assumed moral sense.
Amongst the rational principles of morality, the ontological conception of
perfection, notwithstanding its defects, is better than the theological
conception which derives morality from a Divine absolutely perfect will. The
former is, no doubt, empty and indefinite and consequently useless for finding
in the boundless field of possible reality the greatest amount suitable for
us; moreover, in attempting to distinguish specifically the reality of which
we are now speaking from every other, it inevitably tends to turn in a circle
and cannot avoid tacitly presupposing the morality which it is to explain; it
is nevertheless preferable to the theological view, first, because we have no
intuition of the divine perfection and can only deduce it from our own
conceptions, the most important of which is that of morality, and our
explanation would thus be involved in a gross circle; and, in the next place,
if we avoid this, the only notion of the Divine will remaining to us is a
conception made up of the attributes of desire of glory and dominion, combined
with the awful conceptions of might and vengeance, and any system of morals
erected on this foundation would be directly opposed to morality.
However, if I had to choose between the notion of the moral sense and that
of perfection in general (two systems which at least do not weaken morality,
although they are totally incapable of serving as its foundation), then I
should decide for the latter, because it at least withdraws the decision of
the question from the sensibility and brings it to the court of pure reason;
and although even here it decides nothing, it at all events preserves the
indefinite idea (of a will good in itself free from corruption, until it shall
be more precisely defined.
For the rest I think I may be excused here from a detailed refutation of
all these doctrines; that would only be superfluous labour, since it is so
easy, and is probably so well seen even by those whose office requires them to
decide for one of these theories (because their hearers would not tolerate
suspension of judgement). But what interests us more here is to know that the
prime foundation of morality laid down by all these principles is nothing but
heteronomy of the will, and for this reason they must necessarily miss their
aim.
In every case where an object of the will has to be supposed, in order that
the rule may be prescribed which is to determine the will, there the rule is
simply heteronomy; the imperative is conditional, namely, if or because one
wishes for this object, one should act so and so: hence it can never command
morally, that is, categorically. Whether the object determines the will by
means of inclination, as in the principle of private happiness, or by means of
reason directed to objects of our possible volition generally, as in the
principle of perfection, in either case the will never determines itself
immediately by the conception of the action, but only by the influence which
the foreseen effect of the action has on the will; I ought to do something, on
this account, because I wish for something else; and here there must be yet
another law assumed in me as its subject, by which I necessarily will this
other thing, and this law again requires an imperative to restrict this maxim.
For the influence which the conception of an object within the reach of our
faculties can exercise on the will of the subject, in consequence of its
natural properties, depends on the nature of the subject, either the
sensibility (inclination and taste), or the understanding and reason, the
employment of which is by the peculiar constitution of their nature attended
with satisfaction. It follows that the law would be, properly speaking, given
by nature, and, as such, it must be known and proved by experience and would
consequently be contingent and therefore incapable of being an apodeictic
practical rule, such as the moral rule must be. Not only so, but it is
inevitably only heteronomy; the will does not give itself the law, but is
given by a foreign impulse by means of a particular natural constitution of
the subject adapted to receive it. An absolutely good will, then, the
principle of which must be a categorical imperative, will be indeterminate as
regards all objects and will contain merely the form of volition generally,
and that as autonomy, that is to say, the capability of the maxims of every
good will to make themselves a universal law, is itself the only law which the
will of every rational being imposes on itself, without needing to assume any
spring or interest as a foundation.
How such a synthetical practical a priori proposition is possible, and why
it is necessary, is a problem whose solution does not lie within the bounds of
the metaphysic of morals; and we have not here affirmed its truth, much less
professed to have a proof of it in our power. We simply showed by the
development of the universally received notion of morality that an autonomy of
the will is inevitably connected with it, or rather is its foundation. Whoever
then holds morality to be anything real, and not a chimerical idea without any
truth, must likewise admit the principle of it that is here assigned. This
section then, like the first, was merely analytical. Now to prove that
morality is no creation of the brain, which it cannot be if the categorical
imperative and with it the autonomy of the will is true, and as an a priori
principle absolutely necessary, this supposes the possibility of a synthetic
use of pure practical reason, which however we cannot venture on without first
giving a critical examination of this faculty of reason. In the concluding
section we shall give the principal outlines of this critical examination as
far as is sufficient for our purpose.
Third Section
Transition from the Metaphysic of Morals to the Critique of Pure Practical
Reason
The Concept of Freedom is the Key that explains the Autonomy of the Will
The will is a kind of causality belonging to living beings in so far as
they are rational, and freedom would be this property of such causality that
it can be efficient, independently of foreign causes determining it; just as
physical necessity is the property that the causality of all irrational beings
has of being determined to activity by the influence of foreign causes.
The preceding definition of freedom is negative and therefore unfruitful
for the discovery of its essence, but it leads to a positive conception which
is so much the more full and fruitful.
Since the conception of causality involves that of laws, according to
which, by something that we call cause, something else, namely the effect,
must be produced; hence, although freedom is not a property of the will
depending on physical laws, yet it is not for that reason lawless; on the
contrary it must be a causality acting according to immutable laws, but of a
peculiar kind; otherwise a free will would be an absurdity. Physical necessity
is a heteronomy of the efficient causes, for every effect is possible only
according to this law, that something else determines the efficient cause to
exert its causality. What else then can freedom of the will be but autonomy,
that is, the property of the will to be a law to itself? But the proposition:
"The will is in every action a law to itself," only expresses the
principle: "To act on no other maxim than that which can also have as an
object itself as a universal law." Now this is precisely the formula of
the categorical imperative and is the principle of morality, so that a free
will and a will subject to moral laws are one and the same.
On the hypothesis, then, of freedom of the will, morality together with its
principle follows from it by mere analysis of the conception. However, the
latter is a synthetic proposition; viz., an absolutely good will is that whose
maxim can always include itself regarded as a universal law; for this property
of its maxim can never be discovered by analysing the conception of an
absolutely good will. Now such synthetic propositions are only possible in
this way: that the two cognitions are connected together by their union with a
third in which they are both to be found. The positive concept of freedom
furnishes this third cognition, which cannot, as with physical causes, be the
nature of the sensible world (in the concept of which we find conjoined the
concept of something in relation as cause to something else as effect). We
cannot now at once show what this third is to which freedom points us and of
which we have an idea a priori, nor can we make intelligible how the concept
of freedom is shown to be legitimate from principles of pure practical reason
and with it the possibility of a categorical imperative; but some further
preparation is required.
Freedom must be presupposed as a Property of the Will of all Rational
Beings
It is not enough to predicate freedom of our own will, from Whatever
reason, if we have not sufficient grounds for predicating the same of all
rational beings. For as morality serves as a law for us only because we are
rational beings, it must also hold for all rational beings; and as it must be
deduced simply from the property of freedom, it must be shown that freedom
also is a property of all rational beings. It is not enough, then, to prove it
from certain supposed experiences of human nature (which indeed is quite
impossible, and it can only be shown a priori), but we must show that it
belongs to the activity of all rational beings endowed with a will. Now I say
every being that cannot act except under the idea of freedom is just for that
reason in a practical point of view really free, that is to say, all laws
which are inseparably connected with freedom have the same force for him as if
his will had been shown to be free in itself by a proof theoretically
conclusive.*
Now I affirm that we must attribute to every rational being which has a will
that it has also the idea of freedom and acts entirely under this idea. For in
such a being we conceive a reason that is practical, that is, has causality in
reference to its objects. Now we cannot possibly conceive a reason consciously
receiving a bias from any other quarter with respect to its judgements, for
then the subject would ascribe the determination of its judgement not to its
own reason, but to an impulse. It must regard itself as the author of its
principles independent of foreign influences. Consequently as practical reason
or as the will of a rational being it must regard itself as free, that is to
say, the will of such a being cannot be a will of its own except under the
idea of freedom. This idea must therefore in a practical point of view be
ascribed to every rational being.
* I adopt this method of assuming freedom merely as
an idea which rational beings suppose in their actions, in order to avoid the
necessity of proving it in its theoretical aspect also. The former is
sufficient for my purpose; for even though the speculative proof should not be
made out, yet a being that cannot act except with the idea of freedom is bound
by the same laws that would oblige a being who was actually free. Thus we can
escape here from the onus which presses on the theory.
Of the Interest attaching to the Ideas of Morality
We have finally reduced the definite conception of morality to the idea of
freedom. This latter, however, we could not prove to be actually a property of
ourselves or of human nature; only we saw that it must be presupposed if we
would conceive a being as rational and conscious of its causality in respect
of its actions, i.e., as endowed with a will; and so we find that on just the
same grounds we must ascribe to every being endowed with reason and will this
attribute of determining itself to action under the idea of its freedom.
Now it resulted also from the presupposition of these ideas that we became
aware of a law that the subjective principles of action, i.e., maxims, must
always be so assumed that they can also hold as objective, that is, universal
principles, and so serve as universal laws of our own dictation. But why then
should I subject myself to this principle and that simply as a rational being,
thus also subjecting to it all other being endowed with reason? I will allow
that no interest urges me to this, for that would not give a categorical
imperative, but I must take an interest in it and discern how this comes to
pass; for this properly an "I ought" is properly an "I
would," valid for every rational being, provided only that reason
determined his actions without any hindrance. But for beings that are in
addition affected as we are by springs of a different kind, namely,
sensibility, and in whose case that is not always done which reason alone
would do, for these that necessity is expressed only as an "ought,"
and the subjective necessity is different from the objective.
It seems then as if the moral law, that is, the principle of autonomy of
the will, were properly speaking only presupposed in the idea of freedom, and
as if we could not prove its reality and objective necessity independently. In
that case we should still have gained something considerable by at least
determining the true principle more exactly than had previously been done; but
as regards its validity and the practical necessity of subjecting oneself to
it, we should not have advanced a step. For if we were asked why the universal
validity of our maxim as a law must be the condition restricting our actions,
and on what we ground the worth which we assign to this manner of acting — a
worth so great that there cannot be any higher interest; and if we were asked
further how it happens that it is by this alone a man believes he feels his
own personal worth, in comparison with which that of an agreeable or
disagreeable condition is to be regarded as nothing, to these questions we
could give no satisfactory answer.
We find indeed sometimes that we can take an interest in a personal quality
which does not involve any interest of external condition, provided this
quality makes us capable of participating in the condition in case reason were
to effect the allotment; that is to say, the mere being worthy of happiness
can interest of itself even without the motive of participating in this
happiness. This judgement, however, is in fact only the effect of the
importance of the moral law which we before presupposed (when by the idea of
freedom we detach ourselves from every empirical interest); but that we ought
to detach ourselves from these interests, i.e., to consider ourselves as free
in action and yet as subject to certain laws, so as to find a worth simply in
our own person which can compensate us for the loss of everything that gives
worth to our condition; this we are not yet able to discern in this way, nor
do we see how it is possible so to act — in other words, whence the moral
law derives its obligation.
It must be freely admitted that there is a sort of circle here from which
it seems impossible to escape. In the order of efficient causes we assume
ourselves free, in order that in the order of ends we may conceive ourselves
as subject to moral laws: and we afterwards conceive ourselves as subject to
these laws, because we have attributed to ourselves freedom of will: for
freedom and self-legislation of will are both autonomy and, therefore, are
reciprocal conceptions, and for this very reason one must not be used to
explain the other or give the reason of it, but at most only logical purposes
to reduce apparently different notions of the same object to one single
concept (as we reduce different fractions of the same value to the lowest
terms).
One resource remains to us, namely, to inquire whether we do not occupy
different points of view when by means of freedom we think ourselves as causes
efficient a priori, and when we form our conception of ourselves from our
actions as effects which we see before our eyes.
It is a remark which needs no subtle reflection to make, but which we may
assume that even the commonest understanding can make, although it be after
its fashion by an obscure discernment of judgement which it calls feeling,
that all the "ideas" that come to us involuntarily (as those of the
senses) do not enable us to know objects otherwise than as they affect us; so
that what they may be in themselves remains unknown to us, and consequently
that as regards "ideas" of this kind even with the closest attention
and clearness that the understanding can apply to them, we can by them only
attain to the knowledge of appearances, never to that of things in themselves.
As soon as this distinction has once been made (perhaps merely in consequence
of the difference observed between the ideas given us from without, and in
which we are passive, and those that we produce simply from ourselves, and in
which we show our own activity), then it follows of itself that we must admit
and assume behind the appearance something else that is not an appearance,
namely, the things in themselves; although we must admit that as they can
never be known to us except as they affect us, we can come no nearer to them,
nor can we ever know what they are in themselves. This must furnish a
distinction, however crude, between a world of sense and the world of
understanding, of which the former may be different according to the
difference of the sensuous impressions in various observers, while the second
which is its basis always remains the same, Even as to himself, a man cannot
pretend to know what he is in himself from the knowledge he has by internal
sensation. For as he does not as it were create himself, and does not come by
the conception of himself a priori but empirically, it naturally follows that
he can obtain his knowledge even of himself only by the inner sense and,
consequently, only through the appearances of his nature and the way in which
his consciousness is affected. At the same time beyond these characteristics
of his own subject, made up of mere appearances, he must necessarily suppose
something else as their basis, namely, his ego, whatever its characteristics
in itself may be. Thus in respect to mere perception and receptivity of
sensations he must reckon himself as belonging to the world of sense; but in
respect of whatever there may be of pure activity in him (that which reaches
consciousness immediately and not through affecting the senses), he must
reckon himself as belonging to the intellectual world, of which, however, he
has no further knowledge. To such a conclusion the reflecting man must come
with respect to all the things which can be presented to him: it is probably
to be met with even in persons of the commonest understanding, who, as is well
known, are very much inclined to suppose behind the objects of the senses
something else invisible and acting of itself. They spoil it, however, by
presently sensualizing this invisible again; that is to say, wanting to make
it an object of intuition, so that they do not become a whit the wiser.
Now man really finds in himself a faculty by which he distinguishes himself
from everything else, even from himself as affected by objects, and that is
reason. This being pure spontaneity is even elevated above the understanding.
For although the latter is a spontaneity and does not, like sense, merely
contain intuitions that arise when we are affected by things (and are
therefore passive), yet it cannot produce from its activity any other
conceptions than those which merely serve to bring the intuitions of sense
under rules and, thereby, to unite them in one consciousness, and without this
use of the sensibility it could not think at all; whereas, on the contrary,
reason shows so pure a spontaneity in the case of what I call ideas [ideal
conceptions] that it thereby far transcends everything that the sensibility
can give it, and exhibits its most important function in distinguishing the
world of sense from that of understanding, and thereby prescribing the limits
of the understanding itself.
For this reason a rational being must regard himself qua intelligence (not
from the side of his lower faculties) as belonging not to the world of sense,
but to that of understanding; hence he has two points of view from which he
can regard himself, and recognise laws of the exercise of his faculties, and
consequently of all his actions: first, so far as he belongs to the world of
sense, he finds himself subject to laws of nature (heteronomy); secondly, as
belonging to the intelligible world, under laws which being independent of
nature have their foundation not in experience but in reason alone.
As a rational being, and consequently belonging to the intelligible world,
man can never conceive the causality of his own will otherwise than on
condition of the idea of freedom, for independence of the determinate causes
of the sensible world (an independence which reason must always ascribe to
itself) is freedom. Now the idea of freedom is inseparably connected with the
conception of autonomy, and this again with the universal principle of
morality which is ideally the foundation of all actions of rational beings,
just as the law of nature is of all phenomena.
Now the suspicion is removed which we raised above, that there was a latent
circle involved in our reasoning from freedom to autonomy, and from this to
the moral law, viz.: that we laid down the idea of freedom because of the
moral law only that we might afterwards in turn infer the latter from freedom,
and that consequently we could assign no reason at all for this law, but could
only [present] it as a petitio principii which well disposed minds would
gladly concede to us, but which we could never put forward as a provable
proposition. For now we see that, when we conceive ourselves as free, we
transfer ourselves into the world of understanding as members of it and
recognise the autonomy of the will with its consequence, morality; whereas, if
we conceive ourselves as under obligation, we consider ourselves as belonging
to the world of sense and at the same time to the world of understanding.
How is a Categorical Imperative Possible?
Every rational being reckons himself qua intelligence as belonging to the
world of understanding, and it is simply as an efficient cause belonging to
that world that he calls his causality a will. On the other side he is also
conscious of himself as a part of the world of sense in which his actions,
which are mere appearances [phenomena] of that causality, are displayed; we
cannot, however, discern how they are possible from this causality which we do
not know; but instead of that, these actions as belonging to the sensible
world must be viewed as determined by other phenomena, namely, desires and
inclinations. If therefore I were only a member of the world of understanding,
then all my actions would perfectly conform to the principle of autonomy of
the pure will; if I were only a part of the world of sense, they would
necessarily be assumed to conform wholly to the natural law of desires and
inclinations, in other words, to the heteronomy of nature. (The former would
rest on morality as the supreme principle, the latter on happiness.) Since,
however, the world of understanding contains the foundation of the world of
sense, and consequently of its laws also, and accordingly gives the law to my
will (which belongs wholly to the world of understanding) directly, and must
be conceived as doing so, it follows that, although on the one side I must
regard myself as a being belonging to the world of sense, yet on the other
side I must recognize myself as subject as an intelligence to the law of the
world of understanding, i.e., to reason, which contains this law in the idea
of freedom, and therefore as subject to the autonomy of the will: consequently
I must regard the laws of the world of understanding as imperatives for me and
the actions which conform to them as duties.
And thus what makes categorical imperatives possible is this, that the idea
of freedom makes me a member of an intelligible world, in consequence of
which, if I were nothing else, all my actions would always conform to the
autonomy of the will; but as I at the same time intuite myself as a member of
the world of sense, they ought so to conform, and this categorical
"ought" implies a synthetic a priori proposition, inasmuch as
besides my will as affected by sensible desires there is added further the
idea of the same will but as belonging to the world of the understanding, pure
and practical of itself, which contains the supreme condition according to
reason of the former will; precisely as to the intuitions of sense there are
added concepts of the understanding which of themselves signify nothing but
regular form in general and in this way synthetic a priori propositions become
possible, on which all knowledge of physical nature rests.
The practical use of common human reason confirms this reasoning. There is
no one, not even the most consummate villain, provided only that be is
otherwise accustomed to the use of reason, who, when we set before him
examples of honesty of purpose, of steadfastness in following good maxims, of
sympathy and general benevolence (even combined with great sacrifices of
advantages and comfort), does not wish that he might also possess these
qualities. Only on account of his inclinations and impulses he cannot attain
this in himself, but at the same time he wishes to be free from such
inclinations which are burdensome to himself. He proves by this that he
transfers himself in thought with a will free from the impulses of the
sensibility into an order of things wholly different from that of his desires
in the field of the sensibility; since he cannot expect to obtain by that wish
any gratification of his desires, nor any position which would satisfy any of
his actual or supposable inclinations (for this would destroy the pre-eminence
of the very idea which wrests that wish from him): he can only expect a
greater intrinsic worth of his own person. This better person, however, he
imagines himself to be when be transfers himself to the point of view of a
member of the world of the understanding, to which he is involuntarily forced
by the idea of freedom, i.e., of independence on determining causes of the
world of sense; and from this point of view he is conscious of a good will,
which by his own confession constitutes the law for the bad will that he
possesses as a member of the world of sense — a law whose authority he
recognizes while transgressing it. What he morally "ought" is then
what he necessarily "would," as a member of the world of the
understanding, and is conceived by him as an "ought" only inasmuch
as he likewise considers himself as a member of the world of sense.
Of the Extreme Limits of all Practical Philosophy.
All men attribute to themselves freedom of will. Hence come all judgements
upon actions as being such as ought to have been done, although they have not
been done. However, this freedom is not a conception of experience, nor can it
be so, since it still remains, even though experience shows the contrary of
what on supposition of freedom are conceived as its necessary consequences. On
the other side it is equally necessary that everything that takes place should
be fixedly determined according to laws of nature. This necessity of nature is
likewise not an empirical conception, just for this reason, that it involves
the motion of necessity and consequently of a priori cognition. But this
conception of a system of nature is confirmed by experience; and it must even
be inevitably presupposed if experience itself is to be possible, that is, a
connected knowledge of the objects of sense resting on general laws. Therefore
freedom is only an idea of reason, and its objective reality in itself is
doubtful; while nature is a concept of the understanding which proves, and
must necessarily prove, its reality in examples of experience.
There arises from this a dialectic of reason, since the freedom attributed
to the will appears to contradict the necessity of nature, and placed between
these two ways reason for speculative purposes finds the road of physical
necessity much more beaten and more appropriate than that of freedom; yet for
practical purposes the narrow footpath of freedom is the only one on which it
is possible to make use of reason in our conduct; hence it is just as
impossible for the subtlest philosophy as for the commonest reason of men to
argue away freedom. Philosophy must then assume that no real contradiction
will be found between freedom and physical necessity of the same human
actions, for it cannot give up the conception of nature any more than that of
freedom.
Nevertheless, even though we should never be able to comprehend how freedom
is possible, we must at least remove this apparent contradiction in a
convincing manner. For if the thought of freedom contradicts either itself or
nature, which is equally necessary, it must in competition with physical
necessity be entirely given up.
It would, however, be impossible to escape this contradiction if the
thinking subject, which seems to itself free, conceived itself in the same
sense or in the very same relation when it calls itself free as when in
respect of the same action it assumes itself to be subject to the law of
nature. Hence it is an indispensable problem of speculative philosophy to show
that its illusion respecting the contradiction rests on this, that we think of
man in a different sense and relation when we call him free and when we regard
him as subject to the laws of nature as being part and parcel of nature. It
must therefore show that not only can both these very well co-exist, but that
both must be thought as necessarily united in the same subject, since
otherwise no reason could be given why we should burden reason with an idea
which, though it may possibly without contradiction be reconciled with another
that is sufficiently established, yet entangles us in a perplexity which
sorely embarrasses reason in its theoretic employment. This duty, however,
belongs only to speculative philosophy. The philosopher then has no option
whether he will remove the apparent contradiction or leave it untouched; for
in the latter case the theory respecting this would be bonum vacans, into the
possession of which the fatalist would have a right to enter and chase all
morality out of its supposed domain as occupying it without title.
We cannot however as yet say that we are touching the bounds of practical
philosophy. For the settlement of that controversy does not belong to it; it
only demands from speculative reason that it should put an end to the discord
in which it entangles itself in theoretical questions, so that practical
reason may have rest and security from external attacks which might make the
ground debatable on which it desires to build.
The claims to freedom of will made even by common reason are founded on the
consciousness and the admitted supposition that reason is independent of
merely subjectively determined causes which together constitute what belongs
to sensation only and which consequently come under the general designation of
sensibility. Man considering himself in this way as an intelligence places
himself thereby in a different order of things and in a relation to
determining grounds of a wholly different kind when on the one hand he thinks
of himself as an intelligence endowed with a will, and consequently with
causality, and when on the other he perceives himself as a phenomenon in the
world of sense (as he really is also), and affirms that his causality is
subject to external determination according to laws of nature. Now he soon
becomes aware that both can hold good, nay, must hold good at the same time.
For there is not the smallest contradiction in saying that a thing in
appearance (belonging to the world of sense) is subject to certain laws, of
which the very same as a thing or being in itself is independent, and that he
must conceive and think of himself in this twofold way, rests as to the first
on the consciousness of himself as an object affected through the senses, and
as to the second on the consciousness of himself as an intelligence, i.e., as
independent on sensible impressions in the employment of his reason (in other
words as belonging to the world of understanding).
Hence it comes to pass that man claims the possession of a will which takes
no account of anything that comes under the head of desires and inclinations
and, on the contrary, conceives actions as possible to him, nay, even as
necessary which can only be done by disregarding all desires and sensible
inclinations. The causality of such actions lies in him as an intelligence and
in the laws of effects and actions [which depend] on the principles of an
intelligible world, of which indeed he knows nothing more than that in it pure
reason alone independent of sensibility gives the law; moreover since it is
only in that world, as an intelligence, that he is his proper self (being as
man only the appearance of himself), those laws apply to him directly and
categorically, so that the incitements of inclinations and appetites (in other
words the whole nature of the world of sense) cannot impair the laws of his
volition as an intelligence. Nay, he does not even hold himself responsible
for the former or ascribe them to his proper self, i.e., his will: he only
ascribes to his will any indulgence which he might yield them if he allowed
them to influence his maxims to the prejudice of the rational laws of the
will.
When practical reason thinks itself into a world of understanding, it does
not thereby transcend its own limits, as it would if it tried to enter it by
intuition or sensation. The former is only a negative thought in respect of
the world of sense, which does not give any laws to reason in determining the
will and is positive only in this single point that this freedom as a negative
characteristic is at the same time conjoined with a (positive) faculty and
even with a causality of reason, which we designate a will, namely a faculty
of so acting that the principle of the actions shall conform to the essential
character of a rational motive, i.e., the condition that the maxim have
universal validity as a law. But were it to borrow an object of will, that is,
a motive, from the world of understanding, then it would overstep its bounds
and pretend to be acquainted with something of which it knows nothing. The
conception of a world of the understanding is then only a point of view which
reason finds itself compelled to take outside the appearances in order to
conceive itself as practical, which would not be possible if the influences of
the sensibility had a determining power on man, but which is necessary unless
he is to be denied the consciousness of himself as an intelligence and,
consequently, as a rational cause, energizing by reason, that is, operating
freely. This thought certainly involves the idea of an order and a system of
laws different from that of the mechanism of nature which belongs to the
sensible world; and it makes the conception of an intelligible world necessary
(that is to say, the whole system of rational beings as things in themselves).
But it does not in the least authorize us to think of it further than as to
its formal condition only, that is, the universality of the maxims of the will
as laws, and consequently the autonomy of the latter, which alone is
consistent with its freedom; whereas, on the contrary, all laws that refer to
a definite object give heteronomy, which only belongs to laws of nature and
can only apply to the sensible world.
But reason would overstep all its bounds if it undertook to explain how
pure reason can be practical, which would be exactly the same problem as to
explain how freedom is possible.
For we can explain nothing but that which we can reduce to laws, the object
of which can be given in some possible experience. But freedom is a mere idea,
the objective reality of which can in no wise be shown according to laws of
nature, and consequently not in any possible experience; and for this reason
it can never be comprehended or understood, because we cannot support it by
any sort of example or analogy. It holds good only as a necessary hypothesis
of reason in a being that believes itself conscious of a will, that is, of a
faculty distinct from mere desire (namely, a faculty of determining itself to
action as an intelligence, in other words, by laws of reason independently on
natural instincts). Now where determination according to laws of nature
ceases, there all explanation ceases also, and nothing remains but defence,
i.e., the removal of the objections of those who pretend to have seen deeper
into the nature of things, and thereupon boldly declare freedom impossible. We
can only point out to them that the supposed contradiction that they have
discovered in it arises only from this, that in order to be able to apply the
law of nature to human actions, they must necessarily consider man as an
appearance: then when we demand of them that they should also think of him qua
intelligence as a thing in itself, they still persist in considering him in
this respect also as an appearance. In this view it would no doubt be a
contradiction to suppose the causality of the same subject (that is, his will)
to be withdrawn from all the natural laws of the sensible world. But this
contradiction disappears, if they would only bethink themselves and admit, as
is reasonable, that behind the appearances there must also lie at their root
(although hidden) the things in themselves, and that we cannot expect the laws
of these to be the same as those that govern their appearances.
The subjective impossibility of explaining the freedom of the will is
identical with the impossibility of discovering and explaining an interest*
which man can take in the moral law. Nevertheless he does actually take an
interest in it, the basis of which in us we call the moral feeling, which some
have falsely assigned as the standard of our moral judgement, whereas it must
rather be viewed as the subjective effect that the law exercises on the will,
the objective principle of which is furnished by reason alone.
* Interest is that by which reason becomes
practical, i.e., a cause determining the will. Hence we say of rational beings
only that they take an interest in a thing; irrational beings only feel
sensual appetites. Reason takes a direct interest in action then only when the
universal validity of its maxims is alone sufficient to determine the will.
Such an interest alone is pure. But if it can determine the will only by means
of another object of desire or on the suggestion of a particular feeling of
the subject, then reason takes only an indirect interest in the action, and,
as reason by itself without experience cannot discover either objects of the
will or a special feeling actuating it, this latter interest would only be
empirical and not a pure rational interest. The logical interest of reason
(namely, to extend its insight) is never direct, but presupposes purposes for
which reason is employed.
In order indeed that a rational being who is also affected through the
senses should will what reason alone directs such beings that they ought to
will, it is no doubt requisite that reason should have a power to infuse a
feeling of pleasure or satisfaction in the fulfilment of duty, that is to say,
that it should have a causality by which it determines the sensibility
according to its own principles. But it is quite impossible to discern, i.e.,
to make it intelligible a priori, how a mere thought, which itself contains
nothing sensible, can itself produce a sensation of pleasure or pain; for this
is a particular kind of causality of which as of every other causality we can
determine nothing whatever a priori; we must only consult experience about it.
But as this cannot supply us with any relation of cause and effect except
between two objects of experience, whereas in this case, although indeed the
effect produced lies within experience, yet the cause is supposed to be pure
reason acting through mere ideas which offer no object to experience, it
follows that for us men it is quite impossible to explain how and why the
universality of the maxim as a law, that is, morality, interests. This only is
certain, that it is not because it interests us that it has validity for us
(for that would be heteronomy and dependence of practical reason on
sensibility, namely, on a feeling as its principle, in which case it could
never give moral laws), but that it interests us because it is valid for us as
men, inasmuch as it had its source in our will as intelligences, in other
words, in our proper self, and what belongs to mere appearance is necessarily
subordinated by reason to the nature of the thing in itself.
The question then, "How a categorical imperative is possible,"
can be answered to this extent, that we can assign the only hypothesis on
which it is possible, namely, the idea of freedom; and we can also discern the
necessity of this hypothesis, and this is sufficient for the practical
exercise of reason, that is, for the conviction of the validity of this
imperative, and hence of the moral law; but how this hypothesis itself is
possible can never be discerned by any human reason. On the hypothesis,
however, that the will of an intelligence is free, its autonomy, as the
essential formal condition of its determination, is a necessary consequence.
Moreover, this freedom of will is not merely quite possible as a hypothesis
(not involving any contradiction to the principle of physical necessity in the
connexion of the phenomena of the sensible world) as speculative philosophy
can show: but further, a rational being who is conscious of causality through
reason, that is to say, of a will (distinct from desires), must of necessity
make it practically, that is, in idea, the condition of all his voluntary
actions. But to explain how pure reason can be of itself practical without the
aid of any spring of action that could be derived from any other source, i.e.,
how the mere principle of the universal validity of all its maxims as laws
(which would certainly be the form of a pure practical reason) can of itself
supply a spring, without any matter (object) of the will in which one could
antecedently take any interest; and how it can produce an interest which would
be called purely moral; or in other words, how pure reason can be practicalto
explain this is beyond the power of human reason, and all the labour and pains
of seeking an explanation of it are lost an
It is just the same as if I sought to find out how freedom itself is
possible as the causality of a will. For then I quit the ground of
philosophical explanation, and I have no other to go upon. I might indeed
revel in the world of intelligences which still remains to me, but although I
have an idea of it which is well founded, yet I have not the least knowledge
of it, nor an I ever attain to such knowledge with all the efforts of my
natural faculty of reason. It signifies only a something that remains over
when I have eliminated everything belonging to the world of sense from the
actuating principles of my will, serving merely to keep in bounds the
principle of motives taken from the field of sensibility; fixing its limits
and showing that it does not contain all in all within itself, but that there
is more beyond it; but this something more I know no further. Of pure reason
which frames this ideal, there remains after the abstraction of all matter,
i.e., knowledge of objects, nothing but the form, namely, the practical law of
the universality of the maxims, and in conformity with this conception of
reason in reference to a pure world of understanding as a possible efficient
cause, that is a cause determining the will. There must here be a total
absence of springs; unless this idea of an intelligible world is itself the
spring, or that in which reason primarily takes an interest; but to make this
intelligible is precisely the problem that we cannot solve.
Here now is the extreme limit of all moral inquiry, and it is of great
importance to determine it even on this account, in order that reason may not
on the one band, to the prejudice of morals, seek about in the world of sense
for the supreme motive and an interest comprehensible but empirical; and on
the other hand, that it may not impotently flap its wings without being able
to move in the (for it) empty space of transcendent concepts which we call the
intelligible world, and so lose itself amidst chimeras. For the rest, the idea
of a pure world of understanding as a system of all intelligences, and to
which we ourselves as rational beings belong (although we are likewise on the
other side members of the sensible world), this remains always a useful and
legitimate idea for the purposes of rational belief, although all knowledge
stops at its threshold, useful, namely, to produce in us a lively interest in
the moral law by means of the noble ideal of a universal kingdom of ends in
themselves (rational beings), to which we can belong as members then only when
we carefully conduct ourselves according to the maxims of freedom as if they
were laws of nature.
Concluding Remark
The speculative employment of reason with respect to nature leads to the
absolute necessity of some supreme cause of the world: the practical
employment of reason with a view to freedom leads also to absolute necessity,
but only of the laws of the actions of a rational being as such. Now it is an
essential principle of reason, however employed, to push its knowledge to a
consciousness of its necessity (without which it would not be rational
knowledge). It is, however, an equally essential restriction of the same
reason that it can neither discern the necessity of what is or what happens,
nor of what ought to happen, unless a condition is supposed on which it is or
happens or ought to happen. In this way, however, by the constant inquiry for
the condition, the satisfaction of reason is only further and further
postponed. Hence it unceasingly seeks the unconditionally necessary and finds
itself forced to assume it, although without any means of making it
comprehensible to itself, happy enough if only it can discover a conception
which agrees with this assumption. It is therefore no fault in our deduction
of the supreme principle of morality, but an objection that should be made to
human reason in general, that it cannot enable us to conceive the absolute
necessity of an unconditional practical law (such as the categorical
imperative must be). It cannot be blamed for refusing to explain this
necessity by a condition, that is to say, by means of some interest assumed as
a basis, since the law would then cease to be a supreme law of reason. And
thus while we do not comprehend the practical unconditional necessity of the
moral imperative, we yet comprehend its incomprehensibility, and this is all
that can be fairly demanded of a philosophy which strives to carry its
principles up to the very limit of human reason.
This web edition published by:
eBooks@Adelaide
The University of Adelaide Library
University of Adelaide
South Australia 5005
|