From Marxists Internet Archive
Karl Marx. Capital Volume One
Chapter Fourteen: Division of Labour and Manufacture
Contents
Section 1 - Two-fold Origin of Manufacture
Section 2 - The Detail Labourer and his Implements
Section 3 - The Two Fundamental Forms of Manufacture:
Heterogeneous Manufacture, Serial Manufacture
Section 4 - Division of Labour in Manufacture, and Division of
Labour in Society
Section 5 - The Capitalistic Character of Manufacture
SECTION 1
TWO-FOLD ORIGIN OF MANUFACTURE
That co-operation which is based on division of labour, assumes its typical
form in manufacture, and is the prevalent characteristic form of the capitalist
process of production throughout the manufacturing period properly so called.
That period, roughly speaking, extends from the middle of the 16th to the last
third of the 18th century.
Manufacture takes its rise in two ways:
(1.) By the assemblage, in one workshop under the control of a single
capitalist, of labourers belonging to various independent handicrafts, but
through whose hands a given article must pass on its way to completion. A
carriage, for example, was formerly the product of the labour of a great number
of independent artificers, such as wheelwrigths, harness-makers, tailors,
locksmiths, upholsterers, turners, fringe-makers, glaziers, painters, polishers,
gilders, &c. In the manufacture of carriages, however, all
these different artificers are assembled in one building where they work into
one another’s hands. It is true that a carriage cannot be gilt before it has
been made. But if a number of carriages are being made simultaneously, some may
be in the hands of the gilders while others are going through an earlier
process. So far, we are still in the domain of simple co-operation, which finds
its materials ready to hand in the shape of men and things. But very soon an
important change takes place. The tailor, the locksmith, and the other
artificers, being now exclusively occupied in carriage-making, each gradually
loses, through want of practice, the ability to carry on, to its full extent,
his old handicraft. But, on the other hand, his activity now confined in one
groove, assumes the form best adapted to the narrowed sphere of action. At
first, carriage manufacture is a combination of various independent handicrafts.
By degrees, it becomes the splitting up of carriage-making into its various
detail processes, each of which crystallises
into the exclusive function of a particular workman, the manufacture, as a
whole, being carried on by the men in conjunction. In the same way, cloth
manufacture, as also a whole series of other manufactures, arose by combining
different handicrafts together under the control of a single capitalist. [1]
(2.) Manufacture also arises in a way exactly the reverse of this namely, by
one capitalist employing simultaneously in one workshop a number of artificers,
who all do the same, or the same kind of work, such as making paper, type, or
needles. This is co-operation in its most elementary form. Each of these
artificers (with the help, perhaps, of one or two apprentices), makes the entire
commodity, and he consequently performs in succession all the operations
necessary for its production. He still works in his old handicraft-like way. But
very soon external circumstances cause a different use to be made of the
concentration of the workmen on one spot, and of the simultaneousness of their
work. An increased quantity of the article has perhaps to be delivered within a
given time. The work is therefore re-distributed. Instead of each man being
allowed to perform all the various operations in succession, these operations
are changed into disconnected, isolated ones, carried on side by side; each is
assigned to a different artificer, and the whole of them together are performed
simultaneously by the co-operating workmen. This accidental repartition gets
repeated, develops advantages of its own, and gradually ossifies into a
systematic division of labour. The commodity, from being the individual product
of an independent artificer, becomes the social product of a union of
artificers, each of whom performs one, and only one, of the constituent partial
operations. The same operations which, in the case of a papermaker belonging to
a German Guild, merged one into the other as the successive acts of one
artificer, became in the Dutch paper manufacture so many partial operations
carried on side by side by numerous co-operating labourers. The needlemaker of
the Nuremberg Guild was the cornerstone on
which the English needle manufacture was raised. But while in Nuremberg that
single artificer performed a series of perhaps 20 operations one after another,
in England it was not long before there were 20 needlemakers side by side, each
performing one alone of those 20 operations, and in consequence of further
experience, each of those 20 operations was again split up, isolated, and made
the exclusive function of a separate workman.
The mode in which manufacture arises, its growth out of handicrafts, is
therefore two-fold. On the one hand, it arises from the union of various
independent handicrafts, which become stripped of their independence and
specialised to such an extent as to be reduced to mere supplementary partial
processes in the production of one particular commodity. On the other hand, it
arises from the co-operation of artificers of one handicraft; it splits up that
particular handicraft into its various detail operations, isolating, and making
these operations independent of one another up to the point where each becomes
the exclusive function of a particular labourer. On the one hand, therefore,
manufacture either introduces diversion of labour into a process of production,
or further develops that division; on the other hand, it unites together
handicrafts that were formerly separate. But whatever may have been its
particular starting-point, its final form is invariably the same a productive
mechanism whose parts are human beings.
For a proper understanding of the division of labour in manufacture, it is
essential that the following points be firmly grasped. First, the decomposition
of a process of production into its various successive steps coincides, here,
strictly with the resolution of a handicraft into its successive manual
operations. Whether complex or simple, each operation has to be done by hand,
retains the character of a handicraft, and is therefore dependent on the
strength, skill, quickness, and sureness, of the individual workman in handling
his tools. The handicraft continues to be the basis. This narrow technical basis
excludes a really scientific analysis of any definite process of industrial
production, since it is still a condition that each detail process gone through
by the product must be capable of being done by hand and of forming, in its way,
a separate handicraft. It is just because handicraft skill continues, in this
way, to be the foundation of the process of production, that each workman
becomes exclusively assigned to a partial function, and that for the rest of his
life, his labour-power is turned into the organ of this detail function.
Secondly, this division of labour is a particular sort of co-operation,
and many of its disadvantages spring from the general character of co-operation,
and not from this particular form of it.
SECTION 2
THE DETAIL LABOURER AND HIS IMPLEMENTS
If we now go more into detail, it is, in the first place, clear that a
labourer who all his life performs one and the same simple operation, converts
his whole body into the automatic, specialised implement of that operation.
Consequently, he takes less time in doing it, than the artificer who performs a
whole series of operations in succession. But the collective labourer, who
constitutes the living mechanism of manufacture, is made up solely of such
specialised detail labourers. Hence, in comparison with the independent
handicraft, more is produced in a given time, or the productive power of labour
is increased. [2] Moreover, when once
this fractional work is established as the exclusive function of one person, the
methods it employs become perfected. The workman’s continued repetition of the
same simple act, and the concentration of his attention on it, teach him by
experience how to attain the desired effect with the minimum of exertion. But
since there are always several generations of labourers living at one time, and
working together at the manufacture of a given article, the technical skill, the
tricks of the trade thus acquired, become established, and are accumulated and
handed down. [3]
Manufacture, in fact, produces the skill of the detail labourer, by
reproducing, and systematically driving to an extreme within the workshop, the
naturally developed differentiation of trades which it found ready to hand in
society at large. On the other hand, the conversion of fractional work into the
life-calling of one man, corresponds to the tendency shown by earlier societies,
to make trades hereditary; either to petrify them into castes, or whenever
definite historical conditions beget in the individual a tendency to vary in a
manner incompatible with the nature of castes, to ossify them into guilds.
Castes and guilds arise from the action of the same natural law, that regulates
the differentiation of plants and animals into species and varieties, except
that, when a certain degree of development has been reached, the heredity of
castes and the exclusiveness of guilds are ordained as a law of society. [4]
“The muslins of Dakka in fineness, the calicoes and other piece goods of
Coromandel in brilliant and durable colours, have never been surpassed. Yet they
are produced without capital, machinery, division of labour, or any of those
means which give such facilities to the manufacturing interest of Europe. The
weaver is merely a detached individual, working a web when ordered of a
customer, and with a loom of the rudest construction, consisting sometimes of a
few branches or bars of wood, put roughly together. There is even no expedient
for rolling up the warp; the loom must therefore be kept stretched to its full
length, and becomes so inconveniently large, that it cannot be contained within
the hut of the manufacturer, who is therefore compelled to ply his trade in the
open air, where it is interrupted by every vicissitude of the weather.” [5]
It is only the special skill accumulated from generation to generation, and
transmitted from father to son, that gives to the Hindu, as it does to the
spider, this proficiency. And yet the work of such a Hindu weaver is very
complicated, compared with that of a manufacturing labourer.
An artificer, who performs one after another the various fractional
operations in the production of a finished article, must at one time change his
place, at another his tools. The transition from one operation to another
interrupts the flow of his labour, and creates, so to say, gaps in his
working-day. These gaps close up so soon as he is tied to one and the same
operation all day long; they vanish in proportion as the changes in his work
diminish. The resulting increased productive power is owing either to an
increased expenditure of labour-power in a given time i.e., to increased
intensity of labour or to a decrease in the amount of labour-power
unproductively consumed. The extra expenditure of power, demanded by every
transition from rest to motion, is made up for by prolonging the duration of the
normal velocity when once acquired. On the other hand, constant labour of one
uniform kind disturbs the intensity and flow of a man’s animal spirits, which
find recreation and delight in mere change of activity.
The productiveness of labour depends not only on the proficiency of the
workman, but on the perfection of his tools. Tools of the same kind, such as
knives, drills, gimlets. hammers, &c., may be employed
in different processes; and the same tool may serve various purposes in a
single process. But so soon as the different operations of a
labour-process are disconnected the one from the other, and each fractional
operation acquires in the hands of the detail labourer a suitable and peculiar
form, alterations become necessary in the implements that previously served more
than one purpose. The direction taken by this change is determined by the
difficulties experienced in consequence of the unchanged form of the implement.
Manufacture is characterised by the differentiation of the instruments of labour
a differentiation whereby implements of a given sort acquire fixed shapes,
adapted to each particular application, and by the specialisation of those
instruments, giving to each special implement its full play only in the hands of
a specific detail labourer. In Birmingham alone 500 varieties of hammers are
produced, and not only is each adapted to one particular process, but several
varieties often serve exclusively for the different operations in one and the
same process. The manufacturing period simplifies, improves, and multiplies the
implements of labour, by adapting them to the exclusively special functions of
each detail labourer. [6] It thus
creates at the same time one of the material conditions for the existence of
machinery, which consists of a combination of simple instruments.
The detail labourer and his implements are the simplest elements of
manufacture. Let us now turn to its aspect as a whole.
SECTION 3
THE TWO FUNDAMENTAL FORMS OF MANUFACTURE: HETEROGENEOUS MANUFACTURE, SERIAL
MANUFACTURE
The organisation of manufacture has two fundamental forms which, in spite of
occasional blending, are essentially different in kind, and, moreover, play very
distinct parts in the subsequent transformation of manufacture into modern
industry carried on by machinery. This double character arises from the nature
of the article produced. This article either results from the mere mechanical
fitting together of partial products made independently, or owes its completed
shape to a series of connected processes and manipulations.
A locomotive, for instance, consists of more than 5,000 independent parts. It
cannot, however, serve as an example of the first kind of genuine manufacture,
for it is a structure produced by modern mechanical industry. But a watch can;
and William Petty used it to illustrate the division of labour in manufacture.
Formerly the individual work of a Nuremberg artificer, the watch has been
transformed into the social product of an immense number of detail labourers,
such as mainspring makers, dial makers, spiral spring makers, jewelled hole
makers, ruby lever makers, hand makers, case makers, screw makers, gilders, with
numerous subdivisions, such as wheel makers (brass and steel separate), pin
makers, movement makers, acheveur de pignon (fixes the wheels on the axles,
polishes the facets, &c.), pivot makers, planteur de finissage (puts the
wheels and springs in the works), finisseur de barillet (cuts teeth in the
wheels, makes the holes of the right size, &c.), escapement makers, cylinder
makers for cylinder escapements, escapement wheel makers, balance wheel makers,
raquette makers (apparatus for regulating the watch), the planteur d’échappement
(escapement maker proper); then the repasseur de barillet (finishes the box for
the spring, &c.), steel polishers, wheel polishers, screw polishers, figure
painters, dial enamellers (melt the enamel on the copper), fabricant de pendants
(makes the ring by which the case is hung), finisseur de charnière (puts the
brass hinge in the cover, &c.), faiseur de secret (puts in the springs that
open the case), graveur, ciseleur, polisseur de boîte, &c., &c., and
last of all the repasseur, who fits together the whole watch and hands it over
in a going state. Only a few parts of the watch pass through several hands; and
all these membra disjecta come together for the first time in the hand that
binds them into one mechanical whole. This external relation between the
finished product, and its various and diverse elements makes it, as well in this
case as in the case of all similar finished articles, a matter of chance whether
the detail labourers are brought together in one workshop or not. The detail
operations may further be carried on like so many independent handicrafts, as
they are in the Cantons of Vaud and Neufchâtel; while in Geneva there exist
large watch manufactories where the detail labourers directly co-operate under
the control of a single capitalist. And even
in the latter case the dial, the springs, and the case, are seldom made in the
factory itself. To carry on the trade as a manufacture, with concentration of
workmen, is, in the watch trade, profitable only under exceptional conditions,
because competition is greater between the labourers who desire to work at home,
and because the splitting up of the work into a number of heterogeneous
processes, permits but little use of the instruments of labour in common, and
the capitalist, by scattering the work, saves the outlay on workshops, &c. [7]
Nevertheless the position of this detail labourer who, though he works at home,
does so for a capitalist (manufacturer, établisseur), is very different from
that of the independent artificer, who works for his own customers. [8]
The second kind of manufacture, its perfected form, produces articles that go
through connected phases of development, through a series of processes step by
step, like the wire in the manufacture of needles, which passes through the
hands of 72 and sometimes even 92 different detail workmen.
In so far as such a manufacture, when first started, combines scattered
handicrafts, it lessens the space by which the various phases of production are
separated from each other. The time taken in passing from one stage to another
is shortened, so is the labour that effectuates this passage. [9]
In comparison with a handicraft, productive power is gained, and this gain is
owing to the general co-operative character of manufacture. On the other hand,
division of labour, which is the distinguishing principle of manufacture,
requires the isolation of the various stages of production and their
independence of each other. The establishment and maintenance of a connexion
between the isolated functions necessitates the incessant transport of the
article from one hand to another, and from one process to another. From the
standpoint of modern mechanical industry, this necessity stands forth as a
characteristic and costly disadvantage, and one that is immanent in the
principle of manufacture. [10]
If we confine our attention to some particular lot of raw materials, of rags,
for instance, in paper manufacture, or of wire in needle manufacture, we
perceive that it passes in succession through a series of stages in the hands of
the various detail workmen until completion. On the other hand, if we look at
the workshop as a whole, we see the raw material in all the stages of its
production at the same time. The collective labourer, with one set of his many
hands armed with one kind of tools, draws the wire, with another set, armed with
different tools, he, at the same time, straightens it, with another, he cuts it,
with another, points it, and so on. The different detail processes, which were
successive in time, have become simultaneous, go on side by side in space.
Hence, production of a greater quantum of finished commodities in a given time. [11]
This simultaneity, it is true, is due to the general co-operative form of the
process as a whole; but Manufacture not only finds the conditions for
co-operation ready to hand, it also, to some extent, creates them by the
sub-division of handicraft labour. On the other hand, it accomplishes this
social organisation of the labour-process only by riveting each labourer to a
single fractional detail.
Since the fractional product of each detail labourer is, at the same time,
only a particular stage in the development of one and the same finished article,
each labourer, or each group of labourers, prepares the raw material for another
labourer or group. The result of the labour of the one is the starting-point for
the labour of the other. The one workman therefore gives occupation directly to
the other. The labour-time necessary in each
partial process, for attaining the desired effect, is learnt by experience; and
the mechanism of Manufacture, as a whole, is based on the assumption that a
given result will be obtained in a given time. It is only on this assumption
that the various supplementary labour-processes can proceed uninterruptedly,
simultaneously, and side by side. It is clear that this direct dependence of the
operations, and therefore of the labourers, on each other, compels each one of
them to spend on his work no more than the necessary time, and thus a
continuity, uniformity, regularity, order, [12]
and even intensity of labour, of quite a different kind, is begotten than is to
be found in an independent
handicraft or even in simple co-operation. The rule, that the labour-time
expended on a commodity should not exceed that which is socially necessary for
its production, appears, in the production of commodities generally, to be
established by the mere effect of competition; since, to express ourselves
superficially, each single producer is obliged to sell his commodity at its
market-price. In Manufacture, on the contrary, the turning out of a given
quantum of product in a given time is a technical law of the process of
production itself. [13]
Different operations take, however, unequal periods, and yield therefore, in
equal times unequal quantities of fractional products. If, therefore, the same
labourer has, day after day, to perform the same operation, there must be a
different number of labourers for each operation; for instance, in type
manufacture, there are four founders and two breakers to one rubber: the founder
casts 2,000 type an hour, the breaker breaks up 4,000, and the rubber polishes
8,000. Here we have again the principle of co-operation in its simplest form,
the simultaneous employment of many doing the same thing; only now, this
principle is the expression of an organic relation. The division of labour, as
carried out in Manufacture, not only simplifies and multiplies the qualitatively
different parts of the social collective labourer, but also creates a fixed
mathematical relation or ratio which regulates the quantitative extent of those
parts i.e., the relative number of labourers, or the relative size of the group
of labourers, for each detail operation. It develops, along with the qualitative
sub-division of the social labour-process, a quantitative rule and
proportionality for that process.
When once the most fitting proportion has been experimentally established for
the numbers of the detail labourers in the various groups when producing on a
given scale, that scale can be extended only by employing a multiple of each
particular group. [14] There is this
to boot, that the same individual can do certain kinds of work just as well on a
large as on a small scale; for instance, the labour of superintendence, the
carriage of the fractional product from one stage to the next, &c. The
isolation of such functions, their allotment to a particular labourer, does not
become advantageous till after an increase in the
number of labourers employed; but this increase must affect every group
proportionally.
The isolated group of labourers to whom any particular detail function is
assigned, is made up of homogeneous elements, and is one of the constituent
parts of the total mechanism. In many manufactures, however, the group itself is
an organised body of labour, the total mechanism being a repetition or
multiplication of these elementary organisms. Take, for instance, the
manufacture of glass bottles. It may be resolved into three essentially
different stages. First, the preliminary stage, consisting of the preparation of
the components of the glass, mixing the sand and lime, &c., and melting them
into a fluid mass of glass. [15]
Various detail labourers are employed in this first stage, as also in the final
one of removing the bottles from the drying furnace, sorting and packing them,
&c. In the middle, between these two stages, comes the glass melting proper,
the manipulation of the fluid mass. At each mouth of the furnace, there works a
group, called “the hole,” consisting of one bottlemaker or finisher, one
blower, one gatherer, one putter-up or whetter-off, and one taker-in. These five
detail workers are so many special organs of a single working organism that acts
only as a whole, and therefore can operate only by the direct co-operation of
the whole five. The whole body is paralysed if but one of its members be
wanting. But a glass furnace has several openings (in England from 4 to 6), each
of which contains an earthenware melting-pot full of molten glass, and employs a
similar five-membered group of workers. The organisation of each group is based
on division of labour, but the bond between the different groups is simple
co-operation, which, by using in common one of the means of production, the
furnace, causes it to be more economically consumed. Such a furnace, with its
4-6 groups, constitutes a glass house; and a glass manufactory comprises a
number of such glass houses, together with the apparatus and workmen requisite
for the preparatory and final stages.
Finally, just as Manufacture arises in part from the combination of various
handicrafts, so, too, it develops into a combination of various manufactures.
The larger English glass manufacturers, for instance, make their own earthenware
melting-pots, because, on the quality of these depends, to a great extent, the
success or failure of the process. The manufacture of one of the means of
production is here united with that of the product. On the other hand, the
manufacture of the product may be united with other manufactures, of which that
product is the raw material, or with the products of which it is itself
subsequently
mixed. Thus, we find the manufacture of flint glass combined with that of glass
cutting and brass founding; the latter for the metal settings of various
articles of glass. The various manufactures so combined form more or less
separate departments of a larger manufacture, but are at the same time
independent processes, each with its own division of labour. In spite of the
many advantages offered by this combination of manufactures, it never grows into
a complete technical system on its own foundation. That happens only on its
transformation into an industry carried on by machinery.
Early in the manufacturing period, the principle of lessening the necessary
labour-time in the production of commodities, [16]
was accepted and formulated: and the use of machines, especially for certain
simple first processes that have to be conducted on a very large scale, and with
the application of great force, sprang up here and there. Thus, at an early
period in paper manufacture, the tearing up of the rags was done by paper-mills;
and in metal works, the pounding of the ores was effected by stamping mills. [17]
The Roman Empire had handed down the elementary form of all machinery in the
water-wheel. [18]
The handicraft period bequeathed to us the great inventions of the compass,
of gunpowder, of type-printing, and of the automatic clock. But, on the whole,
machinery played that subordinate part which Adam Smith assigns to it in
comparison with division of labour. [19]
The sporadic use of machinery in the 17th century was of the greatest
importance, because it supplied the great mathematicians of that time with a
practical basis and stimulant to the creation of the science of mechanics.
The collective labourer, formed by the combination of a number of detail
labourers, is the machinery specially characteristic of the manufacturing
period. The various operations that are performed in turns by the producer of a
commodity, and coalesce one with another during the progress of production, lay
claim to him in various ways. In one operation he must exert more strength, in
another more skill, in another more attention; and the same individual does not
possess all these qualities in an equal degree. After
Manufacture has once separated, made independent, and isolated the various
operations, the labourers are divided, classified, and grouped according to
their predominating qualities. If their natural endowments are, on the one hand,
the foundation on which the division of labour is built up, on the other hand,
Manufacture, once introduced, develops in them new powers that are by nature
fitted only for limited and special functions. The collective labourer now
possesses, in an equal degree of excellence, all the qualities requisite for
production, and expends them in the most economical manner, by exclusively
employing all his organs, consisting of particular labourers, or groups of
labourers, in performing their special functions. [20]
The one-sidedness and the deficiencies of the detail labourer become perfections
when he is a part of the collective labourer. [21]
The habit of doing only one thing converts him into a never failing instrument,
while his connexion with the whole mechanism compels him to work with the
regularity of the parts of a machine. [22]
Since the collective labourer has functions, both simple and complex, both
high and low, his members, the individual labour-powers, require different
degrees of training, and must therefore have different values. Manufacture,
therefore, develops a hierarchy of labour-powers, to which there corresponds a
scale of wages. If, on the one hand, the individual labourers are appropriated
and annexed for life by a limited function; on the other hand, the various
operations of the hierarchy are parcelled out among the labourers according to
both their natural and their acquired capabilities. [23]
Every process of production, however,
requires certain simple manipulations, which every man is capable of doing. They
too are now severed from their connexion with the more pregnant moments of
activity, and ossified into exclusive functions of specially appointed labourers.
Hence, Manufacture begets, in every handicraft that it seizes upon, a class of
so-called unskilled labourers, a class which handicraft industry strictly
excluded. If it develops a one-sided speciality into a perfection, at the
expense of the whole of a man’s working capacity, it also begins to make a
speciality of the absence of all development. Alongside of the hierarchic
gradation there steps the simple separation of the labourers into skilled and
unskilled. For the latter, the cost of apprenticeship vanishes; for the former,
it diminishes, compared with that of artificers, in consequence of the functions
being simplified. In both cases the value of labour-power falls. [24]
An exception to this law holds good whenever the decomposition of the labour-process
begets new and comprehensive functions, that either had no place at all, or only
a very modest one, in handicrafts. The fall in the value of labour-power, caused
by the disappearance or diminution of the expenses of apprenticeship, implies a
direct increase of surplus-value for the benefit of capital; for everything that
shortens the necessary labour-time required for the reproduction of labour-power,
extends the domain of surplus-labour.
SECTION 4
DIVISION OF LABOUR IN MANUFACTURE, AND DIVISION OF LABOUR IN SOCIETY
We first considered the origin of Manufacture, then its simple elements, then
the detail labourer and his implements, and finally, the totality of the
mechanism. We shall now lightly touch upon the relation between the division of
labour in manufacture, and the social division of labour, which forms the
foundation of all production of commodities.
If we keep labour alone in view, we may designate the separation of social
production into its main divisions or genera — viz., agriculture,
industries, &c., as division of labour in general, and the splitting up of
these families into species and sub-species, as division of labour in
particular, and the division of labour within the workshop as division of
labour in singular or in detail. [25]
Division of labour in a society, and the corresponding tying down of
individuals to a particular calling, develops itself, just as does the division
of labour in manufacture, from opposite starting-points. Within a family, [26]
and after further development within a tribe, there springs up naturally a
division of labour, caused by differences of sex and age, a division that is
consequently based on a purely physiological foundation, which division enlarges
its materials by the expansion of the community, by the increase of population,
and more especially, by the conflicts between different tribes, and the
subjugation of one tribe by another. On the other hand, as I have before
remarked, the exchange of products springs up at the points where different
families, tribes, communities, come in contact; for, in the beginning of
civilisation, it is not private individuals but families, tribes, &c., that
meet on an independent footing. Different communities find different means of
production, and different means of subsistence in their natural environment.
Hence, their modes of production, and of living, and their products are
different. It is this spontaneously developed difference which, when different
communities come in contact, calls forth the mutual exchange of products, and
the consequent gradual conversion of those products into commodities. Exchange
does not create the differences between the spheres of production, but brings
what are already different into relation, and thus converts them into more or
less inter-dependent branches of the collective production of an enlarged
society. In the latter case, the social division of labour arises from the
exchange between spheres of production, that are originally distinct and
independent of one another. In the former, where the physiological
division of labour is the starting-point, the particular organs of a compact
whole grow loose, and break off, principally owing to the exchange of
commodities with foreign communities, and then isolate themselves so far, that
the sole bond, still connecting the various kinds of work, is the exchange of
the products as commodities. In the one case, it is the making dependent what
was before independent; in the other case, the making independent what was
before dependent.
The foundation of every division of labour that is well developed, and
brought about by the exchange of commodities, is the separation between town and
country. [27] It may be said, that
the whole economic history of society is summed up in the movement of this
antithesis. We pass it over, however, for the present.
Just as a certain number of simultaneously employed labourers are the
material pre-requisites for division of labour in manufacture, so are the number
and density of the population, which here correspond to the agglomeration in one
workshop, a necessary condition for the division of labour in society. [28]
Nevertheless, this density is more or less relative. A relatively thinly
populated country, with well-developed means of communication, has a denser
population than a more numerously populated country, with badly-developed means
of communication; and in this sense the Northern States of the American Union,
for instance, are more thickly populated than India. [29]
Since the production and the circulation of commodities are the general
pre-requisites of the capitalist mode of production, division of labour in
manufacture demands, that division of labour in society at large should
previously have attained a certain degree of development. Inversely, the former
division reacts upon and develops and multiplies the latter. Simultaneously,
with the differentiation of the instruments of labour, the industries that
produce these instruments, become more
and more differentiated.[30] If the
manufacturing system seize upon an industry, which, previously, was carried on
in connexion with others, either as a chief or as a subordinate industry, and by
one producer, these industries immediately separate their connexion, and become
independent. If it seize upon a particular stage in the production of a
commodity, the other stages of its production become converted into so many
independent industries. It has already been stated, that where the finished
article consists merely of a number of parts fitted together, the detail
operations may re-establish themselves as genuine and separate handicrafts. In
order to carry out more perfectly the division of labour in manufacture, a
single branch of production is, according to the varieties of its raw material,
or the various forms that one and the same raw material may assume, split up
into numerous, and to some extent, entirely new manufactures. Accordingly, in
France alone, in the first half of the 18th century, over 100 different kinds of
silk stuffs were woven, and, in Avignon, it was law, that “every apprentice
should devote himself to only one sort of fabrication, and should not learn the
preparation of several kinds of stuff at once.” The
territorial division of labour, which confines special branches of production to
special districts of a country, acquires fresh stimulus from the manufacturing
system, which exploits every special advantage. [31]
The Colonial system and the opening out of the markets of the world, both of
which are included in the general conditions of existence of the manufacturing
period, furnish rich material for developing the division of labour in society.
It is not the place, here, to go on to show how division of labour seizes upon,
not only the economic, but every other sphere of society, and everywhere lays
the foundation of that all engrossing system of specialising and sorting men,
that development in a man of one single faculty at the expense of all other
faculties, which caused A. Ferguson, the master of Adam Smith, to exclaim: “We
make a nation of Helots, and have no free citizens.” [32]
But, in spite of the numerous analogies and links connecting them, division
of labour in the interior of a society, and that in the interior of a workshop,
differ not only in degree, but also in kind. The analogy appears most
indisputable where there is an invisible bond uniting the
various branches of trade. For instance the cattle-breeder produces hides, the
tanner makes the hides into leather, and the shoemaker, the leather into boots.
Here the thing produced by each of them is but a step towards the final form,
which is the product of all their labours combined. There
are, besides, all the various industries that supply the cattle-breeder, the
tanner, and the shoemaker with the means of production. Now it is quite possible
to imagine, with Adam Smith, that the difference between the above social
division of labour, and the division in manufacture, is merely subjective,
exists merely for the observer, who, in a manufacture, can see with one glance,
all the numerous operations being performed on one spot, while in the instance
given above, the spreading out of the work over great areas, and the great
number of people employed in each branch of labour, obscure the connexion. [33]
But what is it that forms the bond between the independent labours of the
cattle-breeder, the tanner, and the shoemaker? It is the fact that their
respective products are commodities. What, on the other hand, characterises
division of labour in manufactures? The fact that the detail labourer produces
no commodities. [34] It is only the
common product of all the detail labourers that becomes a commodity. [35]
Division
of labour in society is brought about by the purchase and sale of the products
of different branches of industry, while the connexion between the detail
operations in a workshop, is due to the sale of the labour-power of several
workmen to one capitalist, who applies it as combined labour-power. The division
of labour in the workshop implies concentration of the means of production in
the hands of one capitalist; the division of labour in society implies their
dispersion among many independent producers of commodities. While within the
workshop, the iron law of proportionality subjects definite numbers of workmen
to definite functions, in the society outside the workshop, chance and caprice
have full play in distributing the producers and their means of production among
the various branches of industry. The different spheres of production, it is
true, constantly tend to an equilibrium: for, on the one hand, while each
producer of a commodity is bound to produce a use-value, to satisfy a particular
social want, and while the extent of these wants differs quantitatively, still
there exists an inner relation which settles their proportions into a regular
system, and that system one of spontaneous growth; and, on the other hand, the
law of the value of commodities ultimately determines how much of its disposable
working-time society can expend on each particular class of commodities. But
this constant tendency to equilibrium, of the various spheres of production, is
exercised, only in the shape of a reaction against the constant upsetting of
this equilibrium. The a priori system on which the division of labour,
within the workshop, is regularly carried out, becomes in the division of labour
within the society, an a posteriori, nature-imposed necessity,
controlling the lawless caprice of the producers, and perceptible in the
barometrical fluctuations of the market-prices. Division of labour within the
workshop implies the undisputed authority of the capitalist over men, that are
but parts of a mechanism that belongs to him. The division of labour within the
society brings into contact independent commodity-producers, who acknowledge no
other authority but that of competition, of the coercion exerted by the pressure
of their mutual interests; just as in the animal kingdom, the bellum omnium
contra omnes [war of all against all – Hobbes]
more or less preserves the conditions of existence of every species. The same
bourgeois mind which praises division of labour in the workshop, life-long
annexation of the labourer to a partial operation, and his complete subjection
to capital, as being an organisation of labour that increases its productiveness
that same bourgeois mind denounces with equal vigour every conscious attempt to
socially control and regulate the process of production,
as an inroad upon such sacred things as the rights of property, freedom and
unrestricted play for the bent of the individual capitalist. It is very
characteristic that the enthusiastic apologists of the factory system have
nothing more damning to urge against a general organisation of the labour of
society, than that it would turn all society into one immense factory.
If, in a society with capitalist production, anarchy in the social division
of labour and despotism in that of the workshop are mutual conditions the one of
the other, we find, on the contrary, in those earlier forms of society in which
the separation of trades has been spontaneously developed, then crystallised,
and finally made permanent by law, on the one hand, a specimen of the
organisation of the labour of society, in accordance with an approved and
authoritative plan, and on the other, the entire exclusion of division of labour
in the workshop, or at all events a mere dwarflike or sporadic and accidental
development of the same. [36]
Those small and extremely ancient Indian communities, some of which have
continued down to this day, are based on possession in common of the land, on
the blending of agriculture and handicrafts, and on an unalterable division of
labour, which serves, whenever a new community is started, as a plan and scheme
ready cut and dried. Occupying areas of from 100 up to several thousand acres,
each forms a compact whole producing all it requires. The chief part of the
products is destined for direct use by the community itself, and does not take
the form of a commodity. Hence, production here is independent of that division
of labour brought about, in Indian society as a whole, by means of the exchange
of commodities. It is the surplus alone that becomes a commodity, and a portion
of even that, not until it has reached the hands of the State, into whose hands
from time immemorial a certain quantity of these products has found its way in
the shape of rent in kind. The constitution of these communities varies in
different parts of India. In those of the simplest form, the land is tilled in
common, and the produce divided among the members. At the same time, spinning
and weaving are carried on in each family as subsidiary industries. Side by side
with the masses thus occupied with one and the same work, we find the “chief
inhabitant,” who is judge, police, and tax-gatherer in one; the book-keeper,
who keeps the accounts of the tillage and registers everything relating thereto;
another official, who prosecutes
criminals, protects strangers travelling through and escorts them to the next
village; the boundary man, who guards the boundaries against neighbouring
communities; the water-overseer, who distributes the water from the common tanks
for irrigation; the Brahmin, who conducts the religious services; the
schoolmaster, who on the sand teaches the children reading and writing; the
calendar-Brahmin, or astrologer, who makes known the lucky or unlucky days for
seed-time and harvest, and for every other kind of agricultural work; a smith
and a carpenter, who make and repair all the agricultural implements; the
potter, who makes all the pottery of the village; the barber, the washerman, who
washes clothes, the silversmith, here and there the poet, who in some
communities replaces the silversmith, in others the schoolmaster. This dozen of
individuals is maintained at the expense of the whole community. If
the population increases, a new community is founded, on the pattern of the old
one, on unoccupied land. The whole mechanism discloses a systematic division of
labour; but a division like that in manufactures is impossible, since the smith
and the carpenter, &c., find an unchanging market, and at the most there
occur, according to the sizes of the villages, two or three of each, instead of
one. [37] The law that regulates the
division of labour in the community acts with the irresistible authority of a
law of Nature, at the same time that each individual artificer, the smith, the
carpenter, and so on, conducts in his workshop all the operations of his
handicraft in the traditional way, but independently, and without recognising
any authority over him. The simplicity of the organisation for production in
these self-sufficing communities that constantly reproduce themselves in the
same form, and when accidentally destroyed, spring up again on the spot and with
the same name [38] this simplicity
supplies the key to the secret of the unchangeableness of Asiatic societies, an
unchangeableness in such striking contrast with the constant dissolution and
refounding of Asiatic States, and the never-ceasing changes of dynasty. The
structure
of the economic elements of society remains untouched by the storm-clouds of
the political sky.
The rules of the guilds, as I have said before, by limiting most strictly the
number of apprentices and journeymen that a single master could employ,
prevented him from becoming a capitalist. Moreover, he could not employ his
journeymen in many other handicrafts than the one in which he was a master. The
guilds zealously repelled every encroachment by the capital of merchants, the
only form of free capital with which they came in contact. A merchant could buy
every kind of commodity, but labour as a commodity he could not buy. He existed
only on sufferance, as a dealer in the products of the handicrafts. If
circumstances called for a further division of labour, the existing guilds split
themselves up into varieties, or founded new guilds by the side of the old ones;
all this, however, without concentrating various handicrafts in a single
workshop. Hence, the guild organisation, however much it may have contributed by
separating, isolating, and perfecting the handicrafts, to create the material
conditions for the existence of manufacture, excluded division of labour in the
workshop. On the whole, the labourer and his means of production remained
closely united, like the snail with its shell, and thus there was wanting the
principal basis of manufacture, the separation of the labourer from his means of
production, and the conversion of these means into capital.
While division of labour in society at large, whether such division be
brought about or not by exchange of commodities, is common to economic
formations of society the most diverse, division of labour in the workshop, as
practised by manufacture, is a special creation of the capitalist mode of
production alone.
SECTION 5
THE CAPITALISTIC CHARACTER OF MANUFACTURE
An increased number of labourers under the control of one capitalist is the
natural starting-point, as well of co-operation generally, as of manufacture in
particular. But the division of labour in manufacture makes this increase in the
number of workmen a technical necessity. The minimum number that any given
capitalist is bound to employ is here prescribed by the previously established
division of labour. On the other hand, the advantages of further division are
obtainable only by adding to the number of workmen, and this can be done only by
adding multiples of the various detail groups. But an increase in the variable
component of the capital employed necessitates an increase in its constant
component, too, in the workshops, implements, &c., and, in particular, in
the raw material, the call for which grows quicker
than the number of workmen. The quantity of it consumed in a given time, by a
given amount of labour, increases in the same ratio as does the productive power
of that labour in consequence of its division. Hence, it is a law, based on the
very nature of manufacture, that the minimum amount of capital, which is bound
to be in the hands of each capitalist, must keep increasing; in other words,
that the transformation into capital of the social means of production and
subsistence must keep extending. [39]
In manufacture, as well as in simple co-operation, the collective working
organism is a form of existence of capital. The mechanism that is made up of
numerous individual detail labourers belongs to the capitalist. Hence, the
productive power resulting from a combination of labours appears to be the
productive power of capital. Manufacture proper not only subjects the previously
independent workman to the discipline and command of capital, but, in addition,
creates a hierarchic gradation of the workmen themselves. While simple
co-operation leaves the mode of working by the individual for the most part
unchanged, manufacture thoroughly revolutionises it, and seizes labour-power by
its very roots. It
converts the labourer into a crippled monstrosity, by forcing his detail
dexterity at the expense of a world of productive capabilities and instincts;
just as in the States of La Plata they butcher a whole beast for the sake of his
hide or his tallow. Not only is the detail work distributed to the different
individuals, but the individual himself is made the automatic motor of a
fractional operation, [40] and the
absurd fable of Menenius Agrippa, which makes man a mere fragment of his own
body, becomes realised. [41] If, at
first, the workman sells his labour-power to capital, because the material means
of producing a commodity fail him, now his very labour-power refuses its
services unless it has been sold to capital. Its functions can be exercised only
in an environment that exists in the workshop of the capitalist after the sale.
By nature unfitted to make anything independently, the manufacturing labourer
develops productive activity as a mere appendage of the capitalist’s
workshop. [42] As the chosen people
bore in their features the sign manual of Jehovah, so division of labour brands
the manufacturing workman as the property of capital.
The knowledge, the judgement, and the will, which, though in ever so small a
degree, are practised by the independent peasant or handicraftsman, in the same
way as the savage makes the whole art of war consist in the exercise of his
personal cunning these faculties are now required only for the workshop as a
whole. Intelligence in production expands in one direction, because it vanishes
in many others. What is lost by the detail labourers, is concentrated in the
capital that employs them. [43] It is
a result of the division of labour in manufactures, that the labourer is brought
face to face with the intellectual potencies of the material process of
production, as the property of another, and as a ruling power. This separation
begins in simple co-operation, where the capitalist represents to the single
workman, the oneness and the will of the associated labour. It is developed in
manufacture which cuts down the labourer into a detail labourer. It is completed
in modern industry, which makes science a productive force distinct from labour
and presses it into the service of capital. [44]
In manufacture, in order to make the collective labourer, and through him
capital, rich in social productive power, each labourer must be made poor in
individual productive powers.
“Ignorance is the mother of industry as well as of
superstition. Reflection and fancy are subject to err; but a habit of moving the
hand or the foot is independent of either. Manufactures, accordingly, prosper
most where the mind is least consulted, and where the workshop may ... be
considered as an engine, the parts of which are men.” [45]
As a matter of fact, some few manufacturers in the middle of the 18th century
preferred, for certain operations that were trade secrets, to employ
half-idiotic persons. [46]
“The understandings of the greater part of men,” says Adam Smith, “are
necessarily formed by their ordinary employments. The man whose whole life is
spent in performing a few simple operations ... has no occasion to exert his
understanding... He generally becomes as stupid and ignorant as it is possible
for a human creature to become.”
After describing the stupidity of the detail labourer he goes on:
“The uniformity of his stationary life naturally corrupts
the courage of his mind... It corrupts even the activity of his body and renders
him incapable of exerting his strength with vigour and perseverance in any other
employments than that to which he has been bred. His dexterity
at his own particular trade seems in this manner to be acquired at the expense
of his intellectual, social, and martial virtues. But in every improved and
civilised society, this is the state into which the labouring poor, that is, the
great body of the people, must necessarily fall.” [47]
For preventing the complete deterioration of the great mass of the people by
division of labour, A. Smith recommends education of the people by the State,
but prudently, and in homeopathic doses. G. Garnier, his French
translator and commentator, who, under the first French Empire, quite naturally
developed into a senator, quite as naturally opposes him on this point.
Education of the masses, he urges, violates the first law of the division of
labour, and with it
“our whole social system would be proscribed.” "Like
all other divisions of labour,” he says, “that between hand labour and head
labour [48] is more pronounced and
decided in proportion as society (he rightly uses this word, for capital, landed
property and their State) becomes richer. This division of labour, like every
other, is an effect of past, and a cause of future progress... ought the
government then to work in opposition to this division of labour, and to hinder
its natural course? Ought it to expend a part of the public money in the attempt
to confound and blend together two classes of labour, which are striving after
division and separation?” [49]
Some crippling of body and mind is inseparable even from division of labour
in society as a whole. Since, however, manufacture carries
this social separation of branches of labour much further, and also, by its
peculiar division, attacks the individual at the very roots of his life, it is
the first to afford the materials for, and to give a start to, industrial
pathology. [50]
“To subdivide a man is to execute him, if he deserves the
sentence, to assassinate him if he does not... The subdivision of labour is the
assassination of a people.” [51]
Co-operation based on division of labour, in other words, manufacture,
commences as a spontaneous formation. So soon as it attains some consistence and
extension, it becomes the recognised methodical and systematic form of
capitalist production. History shows how the division of labour peculiar to
manufacture, strictly so called, acquires the best adapted form at first by
experience, as it were behind the backs of the actors, and then, like the guild
handicrafts, strives to hold fast that form when once found, and here and there
succeeds in keeping it for centuries. Any alteration in this
form, except in trivial matters, is solely owing to a revolution in the
instruments of labour. Modern manufacture wherever it arises I do not here
allude to modern industry based on machinery either finds the disjecta membra
poetae ready to hand, and only waiting to be collected together, as is the case
in the manufacture of clothes in large towns, or it can easily apply the
principle of division, simply by exclusively assigning the various operations of
a handicraft (such as book-binding) to particular men. In such cases, a week’s
experience is enough to determine the proportion between the numbers of the
hands necessary for the various functions. [52]
By decomposition of handicrafts, by specialisation of the instruments of labour,
by the formation of detail labourers, and by grouping and combining the latter
into a single mechanism, division of labour in manufacture creates a qualitative
gradation, and a quantitative proportion in the social process of production; it
consequently creates a definite organisation of the labour of society, and
thereby develops at the same time new productive forces in the society. In its
specific capitalist form and under the given conditions, it could take no other
form than a capitalistic one manufacture is but a particular method of begetting
relative surplus-value, or of augmenting at the expense of the labourer the
self-expansion of capital usually called social wealth, “Wealth of Nations,”
&c. It increases the social productive power of labour, not only for the
benefit of the capitalist instead of for that of the labourer, but it does this
by crippling the individual labourers. It creates new conditions for the
lordship of capital over labour. If, therefore, on the one hand, it presents
itself historically as a progress and as a necessary phase in the economic
development of society, on the other hand, it is a refined and civilised method
of exploitation.
Political Economy, which as an independent science, first sprang into being
during the period of manufacture, views the social division of labour only from
the standpoint of manufacture, [53]
and sees in it only the means of producing more commodities with a given
quantity of labour, and, consequently, of cheapening commodities and hurrying on
the accumulation of capital. In most striking contrast with this accentuation of
quantity and exchange-value, is the attitude of the writers of classical
antiquity, who hold exclusively by quality and use-value. [54]
In consequence of the separation of the social branches of production,
commodities are better made, the various bents and talents of men select a
suitable field, [55] and without some
restraint no important results
can be obtained anywhere. [56] Hence
both product and producer are improved by division of labour. If the growth of
the quantity produced is occasionally mentioned, this is only
done with reference to the greater abundance of use-values. There is not a word
alluding to exchange-value or to the cheapening of commodities. This aspect,
from the standpoint of use-value alone, is taken as well by Plato, [57]
who treats division of labour as the foundation on which the division of society
into classes is based, as by Xenophon, [58]
who with characteristic bourgeois instinct,
approaches more nearly to division of labour within the workshop. Plato’s
Republic, in so far as division of labour is treated in it, as the formative
principle of the State, is merely the Athenian idealisation of the Egyptian
system of castes, Egypt having served as the model of an industrial country to
many of his contemporaries also, amongst others to Isocrates, [59]
and it continued to have this importance to the Greeks of the Roman Empire. [60]
During the manufacturing period proper, i.e., the period during which
manufacture is the predominant form taken by capitalist production, many
obstacles are opposed to the full development of the peculiar tendencies of
manufacture. Although manufacture creates, as we have already seen, a simple
separation of the labourers into skilled and unskilled, simultaneously with
their hierarchic arrangement in classes, yet the number of the unskilled
labourers, owing to the preponderating influence of the skilled, remains very
limited. Although it adapts the detail operations to the various degrees of
maturity, strength, and development of the living instruments of labour, thus
conducing to exploitation of women and children, yet this tendency as a whole is
wrecked on the habits and the resistance of the male labourers. Although the
splitting up of handicrafts lowers the cost of forming the workman, and thereby
lowers his value, yet for the more difficult detail work, a longer
apprenticeship is necessary, and, even where it would be superfluous, is
jealously insisted upon by the workmen. In England, for instance, we find the
laws of apprenticeship, with their seven years’ probation, in full force down
to the end of the manufacturing period; and they are not thrown on one side till
the advent of Modern Industry. Since handicraft skill is the foundation of
manufacture, and since the mechanism of manufacture as a whole possesses no
framework, apart from the labourers themselves, capital is constantly compelled
to wrestle with the insubordination of the workmen.
“By the infirmity of human nature,” says friend Ure, “it
happens that the more skilful the workman,
the more self-willed and intractable he is apt to become, and of course the
less fit a component of a mechanical system in which ... he may do great damage
to the whole.” [61]
Hence throughout the whole manufacturing period there runs the complaint of
want of discipline among the workmen. [62]
And had we not the testimony of contemporary writers, the simple facts, that
during the period between the 16th century and the epoch of Modern Industry,
capital failed to become the master of the whole disposable working-time of the
manufacturing labourers, that manufactures are short-lived, and change their
locality from one country to another with the emigrating or immigrating workmen,
these facts would speak volumes. “Order must in one way or another be
established,” exclaims in 1770 the oft-cited author of the “Essay on Trade
and Commerce.” “Order,” re-echoes Dr. Andrew Ure 66 years later,
“Order” was wanting in manufacture based on “the scholastic dogma of
division of labour,” and “Arkwright created order.”
At the same time manufacture was unable, either to seize upon the production
of society to its full extent, or to revolutionise that production to its very
core. It towered up as an economic work of art, on the broad foundation of the
town handicrafts, and of the rural domestic industries. At a given stage in its
development, the narrow technical basis on which manufacture rested, came into
conflict with requirements of production that were created by manufacture
itself.
One of its most finished creations was the workshop for the production of the
instruments of labour themselves, including especially the complicated
mechanical apparatus then already employed.
A machine-factory, says Ure, “displayed the division of
labour in manifold gradations the file, the drill, the lathe, having each its
different workman in the order of skill.” (P. 21.)
This workshop, the product of the division of labour in manufacture, produced
in its turn machines. It is they that sweep away the handicraftsman’s work as
the regulating principle of social production. Thus, on the one hand, the
technical reason for the life-long annexation of the workman to a detail
function is removed. On the other hand, the fetters that this same principle
laid on the dominion of capital, fall away.
Footnotes
1.
To give a more modern instance: The silk spinning and weaving of Lyon and Nîmes
“est toute patriarcale; elle emploie beaucoup de femmes et d’enfants, mais
sans les épuiser ni les corrompre; elle les laisse dans leur belles valises de
la Drôme, du Var, de l’Isère, de Vaucluse, pour y élever des vers et dévider
leurs cocons; jamais elle n’entre dans une véritable fabrique. Pour être
aussi bien observé ... le principe de la division du travail s’y revêt
d’un caractère spécial. Il y a bien des dévideuses, des moulineurs, des
teinturiers, des encolleurs, puis des tisserands; mais ils ne sont pas réunis
dans un même établissement, ne dépendent pas d’un même maître, tous ils
sont indépendants” [... is entirely patriarchal; it
employs a large number of women and children, but without exhausting or ruining
them; it allows them to stay in their beautiful valleys of the Drôme, the Var,
the Isère, the Vaucluse, cultuvating their silkworms and unwinding their
cocoons; it never becomes a true factory industry. However, the principle of the
division of labour takes on a special character here. There do indeed exist
winders, throwsters. dyers, sizers, and finally weavers; but they are not
assembled in the same workshop, nor are they dependent on a single master; they
are all independent] (A. Blanqui: “Cours, d’Econ. Industrielle.”
Recueilli par A. Blaise. Paris, 1838-39, p. 79.) Since Blanqui wrote this, the
various independent labourers have, to some extent, been united in factories.
[And since Marx wrote the above, the power-loom has invaded these factories, and
is now 1886 rapidly superseding the hand-loom. (Added in the 4th German
edition. The Krefeld silk industry also has its tale to tell anent this
subject.) F. E.]
2.
The more any manufacture of much variety shall be distributed and assigned to
different artists, the same must needs be better done and with greater
expedition, with less loss of time and labour.” (“The Advantages of the East
India Trade,” Lond., 1720, p. 71.)
3.
“Easy labour is transmitted skill.” (Th. Hodgskin, “Popular Political
Economy,” p. 48.)
4.
“The arts also have ... in Egypt reached the requisite degree of perfection.
For it is the only country where artificers may not in any way meddle with the
affairs of another class of citizens, but must follow that calling alone which
by law is hereditary in their clan.... In other countries it is found that
tradesmen divide their attention between too many objects. At one time they try
agriculture, at another they take to commerce, at another they busy themselves
with two or three occupations at once. In free countries, they mostly frequent
the assemblies of the people.... In Egypt, on the contrary, every artificer is
severely punished if he meddles with affairs of State, or carries on several
trades at once. Thus there is nothing to disturb their application to their
calling.... Moreover, since, they inherit from their forefathers numerous rules,
they are eager to discover fresh advantages” (Diodorus Siculus: Bibl. Hist. I.
1. c., 74.)
5.
“Historical and descriptive account of Brit. India, &c.,” by Hugh Murray
and James Wilson, &c., Edinburgh 1832, v. II., p. 449. The Indian loom is
upright, i.e., the warp is stretched vertically.
6.
Darwin in his epoch-making work on the origin of species, remarks, with
reference to the natural organs of plants and animals: “So long as one and the
same organ has different kinds of work to perform, a ground for its
changeability may possibly be found in this, that natural selection preserves or
suppresses each small variation of form less carefully than if that organ were
destined for one special purpose alone. Thus, knives that are adapted to cut all
sorts of things, may, on the whole, be of one shape; but an implement destined
to be used exclusively in one way must have a different shape for every
different use.”
7.
In the year 1854 Geneva produced 80,000 watches, which is not one-fifth of the
production in the Canton of Neufchâtel. La Chaux-de-Fond alone, which we may
look upon as a huge watch manufactory, produces yearly twice as many as Geneva.
From 1850-61 Geneva produced 720,000 watches. See “Report from Geneva on the
Watch Trade” in “Reports by H. M.’s Secretaries of Embassy and Legation on
the Manufactures, Commerce, &c., No. 6, 1863.” The want of connexion
alone, between the processes into which the production of articles that merely
consist of parts fitted together is split up, makes it very difficult to convert
such a manufacture into a branch of modem industry carried on by machinery; but
in the case of a watch there are two other impediments in addition, the
minuteness and delicacy of its parts, and its character as an article of luxury.
Hence their variety, which is such, that in the best London houses scarcely a
dozen watches are made alike in the course of a year. The watch manufactory of
Messrs. Vacheron & Constantin, in which machinery has been employed with
success, produces at the most three or four different varieties of size and
form.
8.
In watchmaking, that classical example of heterogeneous manufacture, we may
study with great accuracy the above-mentioned differentiation and specialisation
of the instruments of labour caused by the sub-division of handicrafts.
9.
“In so close a cohabitation of the people, the carriage must needs be less.”
(“The Advantages of the East India Trade,” p. 106.)
10.
“The isolation of the different stages of manufacture, consequent upon the
employment of manual labour, adds immensely to the cost of production, the loss
mainly arising from the mere removals from one process to another.” (“The
Industry of Nations.” Lond., 1855, Part II, p. 200.)
11.
“It (the division of labour) produces also an economy of time by separating
the work into its different branches, all of which may be carried on into
execution at the same moment.... By carrying on all the different processes at
once, which an individual must have executed separately, it becomes possible to
produce a multitude of pins completely finished in the same time as a single pin
might have been either cut or pointed.” (Dugald Stewart, l.c., p. 319.)
12.
“The more variety of artists to every manufacture... the greater the order and
regularity of every work, the same must needs be done in less time, the labour
must be less.” (“The Advantages,” &c., p. 68.)
13.
Nevertheless, the manufacturing system, in many branches of industry, attains
this result but very imperfectly, because it knows not how to control with
certainty the general chemical and physical conditions of the process of
production.
14.
“When (from the peculiar nature of the produce of each manufactory), the
number of processes into which it is most advantageous to divide it is
ascertained, as well as the number of individuals to be employed, then all other
manufactories which do not employ a direct multiple of this number will produce
the article at a greater cost.... Hence arises one of the causes of the great
size of manufacturing establishments.” (C. Babbage. “On the Economy of
Machinery,” 1st ed. London. 1832. Ch. xxi, pp. 172-73.)
15.
In England, the melting-furnace is distinct from the glass-furnace in which the
glass is manipulated. In Belgium, one and the same furnace serves for both
processes.
16.
This can be seen from W. Petty, John Bellers, Andrew Yarranton, “The
Advantages of the East India Trade,” and J. Vanderlint, not to mention others.
17.
Towards the end of the 16th century, mortars and sieves were still used in
France for pounding and washing ores.
18.
The whole history of the development of machinery can be traced in the history
of the corn mill. The factory in England is still a “mill.” In German
technological works of the first decade of this century, the term “Mühle”
is still found in use, not only for all machinery driven by the forces of
Nature, but also for all manufactures where apparatus in the nature of machinery
is applied.
19.
As will be seen more in detail in the fourth book of this work, Adam Smith has
not established a single new proposition relating to division of labour. What,
however, characterises him as the political economist par excellence of the
period of Manufacture, is the stress he lays on division of labour. The
subordinate part which he assigns to machinery gave occasion in the early days
of modern mechanical industry to the polemic of Lauderdale, and, at a later
period, to that of Ure. A. Smith also confounds differentiation of the
instruments of labour, in which the detail labourers themselves took an active
part, with the invention of machinery; in this latter, it is not the workmen in
manufactories, but learned men, handicraftsman, and even peasants (Brindley),
who play a part.
20.
“The master manufacturer, by dividing the work to be executed into different
processes, each requiring different degrees of skill or of force, can purchase
exactly that precise quantity of both which is necessary for each process;
whereas, if the whole work were executed by one workman, that person must
possess sufficient skill to perform the most difficult, and sufficient strength
to execute the most laborious of the operations into which the article is
divided.” (Ch. Babbage, l.c., ch. xix.)
21.
For instance, abnormal development of some muscles, curvature of bones, &c.
22.
The question put by one of the Inquiry Commissioners, How the young persons are
kept steadily to their work, is very correctly answered by Mr. Wm. Marshall, the
general manager of a glass manufactory: “They cannot well neglect their work;
when they once begin, they must go on; they are just the same as parts of a
machine.” (“Children’s Empl. Comm.,” 4th Rep., 1865, p. 247.)
23.
Dr. Ure, in his apotheosis of Modern Mechanical Industry, brings out the
peculiar character of manufacture more sharply than previous economists, who had
not his polemical interest in the matter, and more sharply even than his
contemporaries Babbage, e.g., who, though much his superior as a mathematician
and mechanician, treated mechanical industry from the standpoint of manufacture
alone. Ure says, “This appropriation ... to each, a workman of appropriate
value and cost was naturally assigned, forms the very essence of division of
labour.” On the other hand, he describes this division as “adaptation of
labour to the different talents of men,” and lastly, characterises the whole
manufacturing system as “a system for the division or gradation of labour,”
as “the division of labour into degrees of skill,” &c. (Ure, l.c., pp.
19-23 passim.)
24.
“Each handicraftsman being ... enabled to perfect himself by practice in one
point, became ... a cheaper workman.” (Ure, l.c., p. 19.)
25.
“Division of labour proceeds from the separation of professions the most
widely different to that division, where several labourers divide between them
the preparation of one and the same product, as in manufacture.” (Storch:
“Cours d’Econ. Pol.,” Paris Edn. t. I., p. 173.) “Nous rencontrons chez
les peuples parvenus à un certain degré de civilisation trois genres de
divisions d’industrie: la première, que nous nommerons générale, amène la
distinction des producteurs en agriculteurs, manufacturiers et commerçants,
elle se rapporte aux trois principales branches d’industrie nationale; la
seconde qu’on pourrait appeler spéciale, est la division de chaque genre
d’industrie en espèces ... la troisième division d’industrie, celle enfin
qu’on devrait qualifier de division de la besogne on de travail proprement dit,
est celle qui s’établit dans les arts et les métiers séparés ... qui s’établit
dans la plupart des manufactures et des ateliers.” [Among
peoples which have reached a certain level of civilisation, we meet with three
kinds of division of labour: the first, which we shall call general, brings
about the division of the producers into agriculturalists, manufacturers, and
traders, it corresponds to the three main branches of the nations’s labour;
the second, which one could call particular, is the division of labour of each
branch into species. ... The third division of labour, which one could designate
as a division of tasks, or of labour properly so called, is that which grows up
in the individual crafts and trades ... which is established in the majority of
the manufactories and workshops] (Skarbek, l.c., pp. 84, 85.)
26.
Note to the third edition. Subsequent very searching study of the
primitive condition of man, led the author to the conclusion, that it was not
the family that originally developed into the tribe, but that, on the contrary,
the tribe was the primitive and spontaneously developed form of human
association, on the basis of blood relationship, and that out of the first
incipient loosening of the tribal bonds, the many and various forms of the
family were afterwards developed. [F. E.]
27.
Sir James Steuart is the economist who has handled this subject best. How little
his book, which appeared ten years before the “Wealth of Nations,” is known,
even at the present time, may be judged from the fact that the admirers of
Malthus do not even know that the first edition of the latter’s work on
population contains, except in the purely declamatory part, very little but
extracts from Steuart, and in a less degree, from Wallace and Townsend.
28.
“There is a certain density of population which is convenient, both for social
intercourse, and for that combination of powers by which the produce of labour
is increased.” (James Mill, l.c., p. 50.) “As the number of labourers
increases, the productive power of society augments in the compound ratio of
that increase, multiplied by the effects of the division of labour.” (Th.
Hodgskin, l.c., pp. 125, 126.)
29.
In consequence of the great demand for cotton after 1861, the production of
cotton, in some thickly populated districts of India, was extended at the
expense of rice cultivation. In consequence there arose local famines, the
defective means of communication not permitting the failure of rice in one
district to be compensated by importation from another.
30.
Thus the fabrication of shuttles formed as early as the 17th century, a special
branch of industry in Holland.
31.
Whether the woollen manufacture of England is not divided into several parts or
branches appropriated to particular places, where they are only or principally
manufactured; fine cloths in Somersetshire, coarse in Yorkshire, long ells at
Exeter, soies at Sudbury, crapes at Norwich, linseys at Kendal, blankets at
Whitney, and so forth.” (Berkeley: “The Querist,” 1751, § 520.)
32.
A. Ferguson: “History of Civil Society.” Edinburgh, 1767; Part iv, sect.
ii., p. 285.
33.
In manufacture proper, he says, the division of labour appears to be greater,
because “those employed in every different branch of the work can often be
collected into the same workhouse, and placed at once under the view of the
spectator. In those great manufactures, (!) on the contrary, which are destined
to supply the great wants of the great body of the people, every different
branch of the work employs so great a number of workmen, that it is impossible
to collect them all into the same workhouse ... the division is not near so
obvious.” (A. Smith: “Wealth of Nations,” bk. i, ch. i.) The celebrated
passage in the same chapter that begins with the words, “Observe the
accommodation of the most common artificer or day-labourer in a civilised and
thriving country,” &c., and then proceeds to depict what an enormous
number and variety of industries contribute to the satisfaction of the wants of
an ordinary labourer, is copied almost word for word from B. de Mandeville’s
Remarks to his “Fable of the Bees, or Private Vices, Publick Benefits.”
(First ed., without the remarks, 1706; with the remarks, 1714.)
34.
“There is no longer anything which we can call the natural reward of
individual labour. Each labourer produces only some part of a whole, and each
part, having no value or utility in itself, there is nothing on which the
labourer can seize, and say: It is my product, this I will keep to myself.”
(“Labour Defended against the Claims of Capital.” Lond., 1825, p. 25.) The
author of this admirable work is the Th. Hodgskin I have already cited.
35.
This distinction between division of labour in society and in manufacture, was
practically illustrated to the Yankees. One of the new taxes devised at
Washington during the civil war, was the duty of 6% “on all industrial
products.” Question: What is an industrial product? Answer of the legislature:
A thing is produced “when it is made,” and it is made when it is ready for
sale. Now, for one example out of many. The New York and Philadelphia
manufacturers had previously been in the habit of “making” umbrellas with
all their belongings. But since an umbrella is a mixtum compositum of
very heterogeneous parts, by degrees these parts became the products of various
separate industries, carried on independently in different places. They entered
as separate commodities into the umbrella manufactory, where they were fitted
together. The Yankees have given to articles thus fitted together, the name of
“assembled articles,” a name they deserve, for being an assemblage of taxes.
Thus the umbrella “assembles,” first, 6% on the price of each of its
elements, and a further 6% on its own total price.
36.
“On peut... établir en règle générale, que moins l’autorité préside à
la division du travail dans l’intérieur de la société, plus la division du
travail se développe dans l’intérieur de l’atelier, et plus elle y est
soumise à l’autorité d’un seul. Ainsi l’autorité dans l’atelier et
celle dans la société, par rapport à la division du travail, sont en raison
inverse l’une de l’autre.” [It can ... be laid down
as a general rule that the less authority presides over the division of labour
inside society, the more the division of labour develops inside the workshop,
and the more it is subjected there to the authority of a single person. Thus
authority in the workshop and authority in society in relation to the division
of labour, are in inverse ratio to each other] (Karl Marx, “Misère,”
&c., pp. 130-131.)
37.
Lieut.-Col. Mark Wilks: “Historical Sketches of the South of India.” Lond.,
1810-17, v. I., pp. 118-20. A good description of the various forms of the
Indian communities is to be found in George Campbell’s “Modern India.”
Lond., 1852.
38.
“Under this simple form ... the inhabitants of the country have lived from
time immemorial. The boundaries of the villages have been but seldom altered;
and though the villages themselves have been sometimes injured, and even
desolated by war, famine, and disease, the same name, the same limits, the same
interests, and even the same families, have continued for ages. The inhabitants
give themselves no trouble about the breaking up and division of kingdoms; while
the village remains entire, they care not to what power it is transferred, or to
what sovereign it devolves; its internal economy remains unchanged.” (Th.
Stamford Raffles, late Lieut. Gov. of Java: “The History of Java.” Lond.,
1817, Vol. I., p. 285.)
39.
“It is not sufficient that the capital” (the writer should have said the
necessary means of subsistence and of production) “required for the
subdivision of handicrafts should be in readiness in the society: it must also
be accumulated in the hands of the employers in sufficiently large quantities to
enable them to conduct their operations on a large scale.... The more the
division increases, the more does the constant employment of a given number of
labourers require a greater outlay of capital in tools, raw material, &c.”
(Storch: “Cours d’Econ. Polit.” Paris Ed., t. I., pp. 250, 251.) “La
concentration des instruments de production et la division du travail sont aussi
inséparables l’une de l’autre que le sont, dans le régime politique, la
concentration des pouvoirs publics et la division des intérêts privés.” [The
concentration of the instruments of production and teh division of labour are as
inseparable one from the other, as are, in the political sphere, teh
concentration of public powers and teh division of private interests.]
(Karl Marx, l.c., p. 134.)
40.
Dugald Stewart calls manufacturing labourers “living automatons ... employed
in the details of the work.” (I. c., p. 318.)
41.
In corals, each individual is, in fact, the stomach of the whole group; but it
supplies the group with nourishment, instead of, like the Roman patrician,
withdrawing it.
42.
“L’ouvrier qui porte dans ses bras tout un métier, peut aller partout
exercer son industrie et trouver des moyens de subsister: l’autre (the
manufacturing labourer) n’est qu’un accessoire qui, séparé de ses confrères,
n’a plus ni capacité, ni indépendance, et qui se trouve force d’accepter
la loi qu’on juge à propos de lui imposer.” [The
worker who is the master of a whole craft can work and find the means of
subsistence anywhere; the other (the manufacturing labourer) is only an
appendage who, when he is separated from his fellows, possesses neither
capability nor independence, and finds himself forced to accept any law it is
thought fit to impose] (Storch, l.c., Petersb. edit., 1815, t. I., p.
204.)
43.
A. Ferguson, l.c., p. 281: “The former may have gained what the other has
lost.”
44.
“The man of knowledge and the productive labourer come to be widely divided
from each other, and knowledge, instead of remaining the handmaid of labour in
the hand of the labourer to increase his productive powers ... has almost
everywhere arrayed itself against labour ... systematically deluding and leading
them (the labourers) astray in order to render their muscular powers entirely
mechanical and obedient.” (W. Thompson: “An Inquiry into the Principles of
the Distribution of Wealth.” London, 1824, p. 274.)
45.
A. Ferguson, l.c., p. 280.
46.
J. D. Tuckett: “A History of the Past and Present State of the Labouring
Population.” Lond., 1846.
47.
A. Smith: “Wealth of Nations,” Bk. v., ch. i, art. ii. Being a pupil of A.
Ferguson who showed the disadvantageous effects of division of labour, Adam
Smith was perfectly clear on this point. In the introduction to his work, where
he ex professo praises division of labour, he indicates only in a
cursory manner that it is the source of social inequalities. It is not till the
5th Book, on the Revenue of the State, that he reproduces Ferguson. In my “Misère
de la Philosophie,” I have sufficiently explained the historical connexion
between Ferguson, A. Smith, Lemontey, and Say, as regards their criticisms of
Division of Labour, and have shown, for the first time, that Division of Labour
as practised in manufactures, is a specific form of the capitalist mode of
production.
48.
Ferguson had already said, l.c., p. 281: “And thinking itself, in this age of
separations, may become a peculiar craft.”
49.
G. Garnier, vol. V. of his translation of A. Smith, pp. 4-5.
50.
Ramazzini, professor of practical medicine at Padua, published in 1713 his work
“De morbis artificum,” which was translated into French 1781, reprinted 1841
in the “Encyclopédie des Sciences Médicales. 7me Dis. Auteurs Classiques.”
The period of Modern Mechanical Industry has, of course, very much enlarged his
catalogue of labour’s diseases. See “Hygiène physique et morale de
l’ouvrier dans les grandes villes en général et dans la ville de Lyon en
particulier. Par le Dr. A. L. Fonteret, Paris, 1858,” and “Die Krankheiten,
welche verschiednen Ständen, Altern und Geschlechtern eigenthümlich sind. 6
Vols. Ulm, 1860,” and others. In 1854 the Society of Arts appointed a
Commission of Inquiry into industrial pathology. The list of documents collected
by this commission is to be seen in the catalogue of the “Twickenham Economic
Museum.” Very important are the official “Reports on Public Health.” See
also Eduard Reich, M. D. “Ueber die Entartung des Menschen,” Erlangen, 1868.
51.
(D. Urquhart: “Familiar Words.” Lond., 1855, p. 119.) Hegel held very
heretical views on division of labour. In his “Rechtsphilosophie” he says:
“By well educated men we understand in the first instance, those who can do
everything that others do.”
52.
The simple belief in the inventive genius exercised a priori by the individual
capitalist in division of labour, exists now-a-days only among German
professors, of the stamp of Herr Roscher, who, to recompense the capitalist from
whose Jovian head division of labour sprang ready formed, dedicates to him
“various wages” (diverse Arbeitslöhne). The more or less extensive
application of division of labour depends on length of purse, not on greatness
of genius.
53.
The older writers, like Petty and the anonymous author of “Advantages of the
East India Trade,” bring out the capitalist character of division of labour as
applied in manufacture more than A. Smith does.
54.
Amongst the moderns may be excepted a few writers of the 18th century, like
Beccaria and James Harris, who with regard to division of labour almost entirely
follow the ancients. Thus, Beccaria: “Ciascuno prova coll’esperienza, che
applicando la mano e l’ingegno sempre allo stesso genere di opere e di
produtte, egli più facili, più abbondanti e migliori ne traca risultati, di
quello che se ciascuno isolatamente le cose tutte a se necessarie soltanto
facesse.... Dividendosi in tal maniera per la comune e privata utilità gli
uomini in varie classi e condizioni.” [Everyone knows
from experience that if the hands and the intelligence are always applied to the
same kind of work and the same products, these will be produced more easily, in
greater abundance, and in higher quality, than if each individual makes for
himself all the things he needs ... In this way, men are divided up into various
classes and conditions, to their own advantage and to that of the commodity.](Cesare
Beccaria: “Elementi di Econ: Pubblica,” ed. Custodi, Parte Moderna, t. xi,
p. 29.) James Harris, afterwards Earl of Malmesbury, celebrated for the
“Diaries” of his embassy at St. Petersburg, says in a note to his
“Dialogue Concerning Happiness,” Lond., 1741, reprinted afterwards in
“Three Treatises, 3 Ed., Lond., 1772: “The whole argument to prove society
natural (i.e., by division of employments) ... is taken from the second book of
Plato’s Republic.”
55.
Thus, in the Odyssey xiv., 228, [“Alloς gar
talloisin aner epiterpetai ergoiς” For
different men take joy in different works] and Archilochus in Sextus
Empiricus, [“alloς allw ep
ergo kardihn iainetai.” men differ as to things
cheer their hearts]
56.
[“Poll hpistaio erga, cacwς d
hpistano panta.” He could do many works, but all
of them badly – Homer] Every Athenian considered himself superior as a
producer of commodities to a Spartan; for the latter in time of war had men
enough at his disposal but could not command money, as Thucydides makes Pericles
say in the speech inciting the Athenians to the Peloponnesian war: [“swmasi
te etoimoteroi oi autonrgoi twn anthrwpwn h crhmasi polemein” people
producing for their own consumption will rather let war have their bodies than
their money] (Thuc.: 1, I. c. 41.) Nevertheless, even with regard to
material production, [autarceia self-sufficiency],
as opposed to division of labour remained their ideal, [“parwn
gar to, eu, para toutwn cai to autaresς.” For
with the latter there is well-being, but with the former there is independence.]
It should be mentioned here that at the date of the fall of the 30 Tyrants there
were still not 5,000 Athenians without landed property.
57.
With Plato, division of labour within the community is a development from the
multifarious requirements, and the limited capacities of individuals. The main
point with him is, that the labourer must adapt himself to the work, not the
work to the labourer; which latter is unavoidable, if he carries on several
trades at once, thus making one or the other of them subordinate. [“Ou
gar ethelei to prattomenon ten tou prattonios scholen perimenein, all anagke ton
prattonta to prattomeno epakoloothein me en parergou merei. Anagke. Ek de touton
pleio te ekasta gignetai kai kallion kai raon, otan eis en kaia physin kai en
kairo scholen ton allon agon, pratte.” [For the
workman must wait upon the work; it will not wait upon his leisure and allow
itself to be done in a spare moment. — Yes, he must,— So the conclusion is
that more will be produced of every thing and the work will be more easily and
better done, when every man is set free from all other occupations to do, at the
right time, the one thing for which he is naturally fitted.] (Rep. 1. 2.
Ed. Baiter, Orelli, &c.) So in Thucydides, l.c., c. 142: “Seafaring is an
art like any other, and cannot, as circumstances require, be carried on as a
subsidiary occupation; nay, other subsidiary occupations cannot be carried on
alongside of this one.” If the work, says Plato, has to wait for the labourer,
the critical point in the process is missed and the article spoiled, [“ergou
cairon diollutai.” [If someone lets slip ...]
The same Platonic idea is found recurring in the protest of the English
bleachers against the clause in the Factory Act that provides fixed mealtimes
for all operatives. Their business cannot wait the convenience of the workmen,
for “in the various operations of singeing, washing, bleaching, mangling,
calendering, and dyeing, none of them can be stopped at a given moment without
risk of damage ... to enforce the same dinner hour for all the workpeople might
occasionally subject valuable goods to the risk of danger by incomplete
operations.” Le platonisme où va-t-il se nicher! [Where
will Platonism be found next!]
58.
Xenophon says, it is not only an honour to receive food from the table of the
King of Persia, but such food is much more tasty than other food. “And there
is nothing wonderful in this, for as the other arts are brought to special
perfection in the great towns, so the royal food is prepared in a special way.
For in the small towns the same man makes bedsteads, doors, ploughs, and tables:
often, too, he builds houses into the bargain, and is quite content if he finds
custom sufficient for his sustenance. It is altogether impossible for a man who
does so many things to do them all well. But in the great towns, where each can
find many buyers, one trade is sufficient to maintain the man who carries it on.
Nay, there is often not even need of one complete trade, but one man makes shoes
for men, another for women. Here and there one man gets a living by sewing,
another by cutting out shoes; one does nothing but cut out clothes, another
nothing but sew the pieces together. It follows necessarily then, that he who
does the simplest kind of work, undoubtedly does it better than anyone else. So
it is with the art of cooking.” (Xen. Cyrop. I. viii., c. 2.) Xenophon here
lays stress exclusively upon the excellence to be attained in use-value,
although he well knows that the gradations of the division of labour depend on
the extent of the market.
59.
He (Busiris) divided them all into special castes ... commanded that the same
individuals should always carry on the same trade, for he knew that they who
change their occupations become skilled in none; but that those who constantly
stick to one occupation bring it to the highest perfection. In truth, we shall
also find that in relation to the arts and handicrafts, they have outstripped
their rivals more than a master does a bungler; and the contrivances for
maintaining the monarchy and the other institutions of their State are so
admirable that the most celebrated philosophers who treat of this subject praise
the constitution of the Egyptian State above all others. (Isocrates, Busiris, c.
8.)
60.
Cf. Diodorus Siculus.
61.
Ure, l.c., p. 20.
62.
This is more the case in England than in France, and more in France than in
Holland.
Transcribed by Hinrich Kuhls
Html Markup by Stephen Baird (1999)
|